Monday, March 23, 2015

Chapter 4_The New Picture

Introduction

Quantum Mechanics

QM is characterized by several substantial departures from classical physics; of these, only determinism is relevant to our present concerns. Classical mechanics is deterministic in the following sense. Suppose you are given an initial configuration of a material system – that is, a system of particles together with their positions, masses and velocities – at a time t Now consider any time t* future with respect to t; if the system is causally closed, there is just one outcome consistent with classical mechanics…Things are very different for QM. The Schrodinger equation for a system S – a system of particles, for example – associates a wave function with S; in essence, for any future time t, the wave function assigns a complex number to each of the many configurations possible for S at t. This wave function is used (via “Born’s Rule”) to assign a certain probability to each possible configuration c for S at t: the probability of finding S in c at t. The point, here, is that (in contrast with classical mechanics) we don’t get a prediction of a unique configuration for the system at t, but only a distribution of probabilities across many possible outcomes. Given a quantum mechanical system, therefore, QM doesn’t say which configuration will in fact result from the initial conditions; instead, it assigns a spectrum of probabilities to the possible outcomes.[1]

On p. 99, Plantinga quotes John Earman, who defines a miracle as “an event that is incompatible with (what we presume, on the basis of the best evidence, to be) laws of nature.” As such, he says that the classic Biblical examples aren’t technically miracles at all, since they are not incompatible with QM.

Q1: Is this the right definition of miracle? How does Plantinga understand a miracle?

On pp. 98-100, Plantinga quotes several experts to support his claim that at least some Biblical miracles are completely compatible with QM.

Q2: What does it mean to say that these miracles are “possible” on QM? Does QM really make the reality of miracles any more plausible? Does the scale of typical miracles effectively rule out the possibility that they will occur, even on QM?  

II. What is the Problem with “Intervention”?

Divine Action Project (DAP) – The main problem for the project is to find an account of divine action in the world – action beyond creation and conservation – that doesn’t involve God’s intervening the world.[2]

Plantinga: What are the problems evoked “for a rationally coherent belief in God as the creator of that order”? Why should we expect God to avoid intervention?

(1)  Connection to the problem of evil

George Ellis: …What one would like here – if one is to make sense of the idea of miracles – is some kind of rock-solid criterion of choice underlying such decisions to act in a miraculous manner, for if there is the necessity to hold to these laws during times of the persecutions and Hitler’s Final Solution, during famines and floods, in order that morality be possible, then how can it be that sometimes this iron necessity can fade away and allow turning water to win or the raising of Lazarus?[3]

à Plantinga: [Paraphrased] Requiring a rock-solid criterion is asking too much. God only needs a good reason to act; he need not make that reason known to us. We could be in a situation like Job.[4]

Q3: Do you think it’s reasonable for human beings to expect to be able to make sense of God’s action in the world? Why or why not? Does the apparent arbitrariness of miraculous occurrences in the world provide humans with any justification for denying God’s existence? [5]

Q4: Does creating something give you the right to do whatever you want with it? What if that thing is a living, autonomous creature (rather than, say, an inanimate clay pot)? Why or why not?

(2)  Fixed, regular laws are requisite for the exercise of free will

George Ellis: [I]t seems probable that fixed laws of behavior of matter, independent of interference by a Creator or any other agency, is a requisite basis of existence of independent beings able to exercise free will, for they make possible meaningful complex organized activity without outside interference (physical laws providing a determinate frame within which definite local causal relations are possible).[6]

à Plantinga: What’s at issue here is not so much freedom; Ellis’s point, I take it, is that if God constantly intervened, the regularities we must rely on in deciding how to act would be absent…[W]hat counts with respect to the possibility of intelligent free action isn’t really the absence of divine intervention, it is rather regularity and predictability. Intelligent free action would not be possible in a world without regularity and predictability, even if God never intervened in it; such action would be possible in a world in which God often intervened, provided he did so in a regular and predictable way.[7]

Plantinga: What’s required for free action is that there be enough regularity for us to know or sensibly conjecture – at least for the most part and with reasonably high probability – what will happen if we freely choose to take a given action…All that’s required for purposeful free action is reasonable confidence in substantial regularity in the neighborhood of the proposed action. And that’s certainly compatible with God’s sometimes intervening.[8]

Q5: Given how resistant the future is to prediction already, even assuming the perfect regularity of nature’s processes,[9] do you think divine interference really introduces further difficulty?

(3)  “The divine consistency objection” – Miracles cannot be interpreted in terms of supernatural interference in natural processes. If such an interpretation were true, the manifestation of the ground of being would destroy the structure of being; God would be split within himself.”[10]

Philip Clayton: “the real problem here, apparently, is that it is very difficult to come up with an idea of divine action in the world in which such action would not constitute ‘breaking natural law.’”[11]

Wesley Wildman: [T]he idea of God sustaining nature and its law-like regularities with one hand while miraculously intervening, abrogating or ignoring those regularities with the other hand struck most members as dangerously close to outright contradiction. Most participants certainly felt that God would not create an orderly world in which it was impossible for the creator to act without violating the created structure of order.[12]

à Plantinga: [These objectors] still seem to display a list in the Laplacean direction: Clayton speaks of God’s “breaking” natural laws, and Saunders…speaks of “overriding” the laws of nature by performing miracles. As I argued earlier, however, it’s exceedingly difficult to see how God could override of “break” natural laws by miraculous healings or raising someone from the dead; under the new picture it’s doubtful that these things are precluded by quantum mechanical laws, even if we set aside the proviso according to which these laws apply only to close systems.[13]

Objection: God simply wouldn’t treat the stuff he has made in starkly different ways; this sort of action is inconsistent with his unfathomable augustness and unsurpassable greatness…[T]here is something arbitrary and whimsical in “dealing in two different manners” with the cosmic process.[14]

à Plantinga: There would be arbitrariness and inconsistency only if God had no special reason for acting contrary to the usual regularities; but of course he might very well have such reasons…Perhaps he aims to establish basic regularities, thus making science and free intelligent action possible for his creatures. But perhaps he also has good reason for sometimes acting contrary to those regularities: to mark special occasions, for example, or to make clear his love or his power, or to authorize what someone says, or to guide history in a certain direction.[15]

Q6: Do you think that intervening in the natural order would reflect arbitrariness or inconsistency on God’s part? Why or why not?

Michael Murray: There is something grand, beautiful and artful about a universe which contains within it everything that is necessary in order for it to bring about the results God intends for it. God could cause every event that we see in the natural world directly. But a powerful and rational designer would…display his power and reason far more manifestly in a universe which is itself a machine-making machine. A universe which achieved the ends God has for it in this self-contained fashion does as much to express the glory of its creator as do the end-products of the creative process.[16]

Q7: Do you agree with the members of Divine Action Project that God’s action in the world should be non-interventionist? What considerations motivate your position?

III. What is Intervention?

Plantinga: What, from the point of view of the new picture, is intervention? Can we so much as say what it consists in?

(1)  An action that causes an event E which is contrary to a natural law

à No good, because a the form of a natural law is “When the universe is causally closed, P.”[17]

(2)  A divine act producing an event that would not have occurred but for that act

à No good because “any act of conservation meets that condition, and conservation is not a case of intervention.”[18]

(3)  An intervention will have occurred at the first time t* such that S(t0)L does not entail S(t*); OR
(4)  Let t* be the first time after t such that S(t*) is not entailed by S(t0) & L: an intervention will have occurred at t*.

à This doesn’t tell us what an intervention is.[19]

(5)  An intervention is an action (divine, demonic, angelic, human) that causes an event E to occur at time t, such that for some t* prior to t, S(t*)&L doesn’t entail that E occurs at t.

à No good because this definition entails that acts of sustaining (e.g., a full-grown horse created ex nihilo) count as intervention, which it shouldn’t.[20]

(6)  (INT) An act A (divine, demonic, angelic, human) is an intervention just if A causes an event E to occur at a time t, where there is an interval of times bounded above by t such that for very time t* in that interval, S(t*)&L doesn’t entail that E occurs at t.[21]

à Plantinga: (INT) works for the classical context, but won’t work in the QM context…Given the indeterminism of [QM], nothing like (INT) is available?...[H]ow could God set aside or override the probabilistic laws of quantum mechanics in performing those miraculous acts?[22]

(7)  An intervention occurs when God performs an action, the consequence of which is an event that would not have occurred had God not performed that action.[23]

à No good, entails that conservation is intervention.

(8)  God intervenes if and only if he performs an action A thereby causing an event E that (a) goes beyond conservation and creation, and (b) is such that if he had not performed A, E would not have occurred.[24]

à No good, because this fails to differentiate between intervention, so construed, and special divine action. The project is to find a conception of special divine action – divine action that goes beyond conservation and creation – that doesn’t involve intervention; if (8) is true, however, every case of special divine action will automatically be a case of intervention – thus making the whole project of trying to find a conception of special divine action that doesn’t involve intervention look a little unlikely.[25]

Q8: What is the difference for Plantinga between intervention and special divine action?

à It seems that what Plantinga is after is an account of special divine action that:
(a)   Coheres with QM
(b)  Doesn’t involve breaking the natural laws (satisfies the conditions of the DAP)
(c)   Differentiates between the acts of creation, conservation, and intervention.

Q9: Why doesn’t Plantinga simply use the same solution in this chapter that he used in the last, i.e., deny that we live in a closed system? Does QM add any new difficulty for this solution? If so, what is it?

(9)  Violating the created structured order[26]

à Plantinga: What are these created structures of order and regularity? Presumably they aren’t the natural laws as disclosed in QM – once again, God’s performing a miracle wouldn’t violate them. So what are they?[27]

IV. Intervention and Divine Action at the Quantum Level

The chief objection…is twofold. First, there is that concern with intervention as somehow going against the natures of the things God has created. And second, there is that alleged “inconsistency”: as McMullin puts it with admirable succinctness, for God to intervene is for him to “deal in two different manners” with the cosmos he created.[28]

William Pollard (1958): God acts at the quantum level.[29]

Copenhagen interpretation: God can cause quantum events, and, because the laws are merely statistical, do so without “suspending” those laws. This action on his part can perhaps be amplified – by chaotic effects or in other ways – to the macroscopic level; in this way, perhaps, God can cause dramatic effects at the level of everyday life, and do so without falling into intervention.[30]

Polkinghorne: Occasions of measurement only occur from time to time, and a God who acted through being their determinator would also only be acting from time to time. Such an episodic account of providential agency does not seem altogether satisfactory theologically.[31]

Q10: Does anyone here think that QM is well enough understood to lend any additional credibility to particular theological views? How could any of them be tested or confirmed? What predictions do they make?

GRW interpretation: On this approach we could think of the nature of a system as dictating that collapses occur at the regular rate they in fact display. What is presently of significance, however, is that on these approaches there is no cause for a given collapse to go to the particular value (the particular position, for example) or eigenstate to which in fact it goes. That is, there is no physical cause; there is nothing in the previous physical state of the world that causes a given collapse to go to the particular eigenstate to which is does go.[32]

On this view of God’s special action – call it “divine collapse-causation” (“DCC”) – God is always acting specially, that is, always acting in ways that go beyond creation and conservation, thus obviating the problem alleged to lie in his sometimes treating the world in hands-off fashion but other times in a hands-on way.
            Furthermore, if, as one assumes, the macroscopic physical world supervenes on the microscopic, God could thus control what happens at the macroscopic level by causing the right microscopic collapse-outcomes. In this way God can exercise providential guidance over cosmic history.[33]

Objection: “Isn’t it part of the very nature of such a system to collapse in such a way as not to violate the probabilities assigned by Born’s Rule? And wouldn’t God’s causing the collapses in fact violate those probabilities? Wouldn’t there have to be something like a divine statistical footprint, if God caused these collapses?”[34]

à Plantinga: This rests on a misunderstanding: all collapses are unlikely, so there’s no guarantee that God’s involvement in the process would yield a noticeably different result than any alternative.[35]

Q11: Is Plantinga right that the difference between natural collapses (those that are described by Born’s Rule) and divine-causes collapses wouldn’t reveal any statistical differences? Or does Plantinga think that DCC, if true, is what is described by Born’s Rule (i.e., the “nature” is just a pseudonym for God)?

Objection: [D]oesn’t this result in divine determinism perhaps even occasionalism, in that God really causes whatever happens at the macro-level?[36]

à Plantinga: Maybe humans also cause collapses to occur, so that we too can freely cause events in the physical world via causing the requisite collapses in our brains.[37]

The thought would be that God’s action constitutes a theater or setting for free actions on the part of human beings and other persons – principalities, powers, angels, Satan and his minions, whatever. God sets the stage for such free action by causing a world of regularity and predictability; but he causes only some of the collapse outcomes, leaving it to free persons to cause the rest.[38]

Objection: DCC is tied to a particular version of QM. What happens if that version gets jettisoned? Indeed, what happens in QM itself gets jettisoned or seriously revised?

à Plantinga: First: if Christian belief is true, the warrant for belief in special divine action doesn’t come from quantum mechanics or current science or indeed any science at all; these beliefs have their own independent source of warrant.[39]

The sensible religious believer I not obliged to trim her sails to the current scientific breeze on this topic revising her belief on the topic every time science changes its mind; if the most satisfactory Christian (or theistic) theology endorses the idea that the universe did indeed have a beginning, the believer has a perfect right to accept that thought. Something similar goes for the Christian believer and special divine action.[40]

Q12: Is Plantinga exaggerating the scale or significance of the change of mind within the scientific community?

V. A Couple of Other Alleged Conflicts

Claim 1: Some people claims that science, taken as a whole, somehow supports or underwrites a naturalistic view of the universe, one in which there is no such person as God or any other supernatural being.[41]

à Plantinga: No it doesn’t, and in fact the opposite is the case (as I’ll demonstrate in Ch. 10).

Claim 2 (or subclaim 1.2): There is a deep difference between religion and science – one that doesn’t redound to the credit of religion…[T]here is a profound contrast between what we might call the epistemic styles of religion and science. The scientist…holds her beliefs tentatively, dispassionately, only on the basis of evidence, and is always looking for a better hypothesis, one that is better supported by the evidence. The religious believer, on the other hand, typically holds his beliefs dogmatically: he is unwilling to consider the evidence and often holds his beliefs with a degree of firmness out of proportion to their support by the evidence; he is unwilling to look for a better hypothesis.[42]

à Plantinga: Scientists don’t hold their beliefs dispassionately, nor do they easily relinquish them in the face of contrary evidence. But even grating Worrall’s characterization of the epistemic practices of scientists versus religious people is true, this difference indicates a science/religion conflict only if science tells us that beliefs in all the areas of our epistemic life ought to be formed and held in the same way as scientific beliefs typically are. But of course that isn’t a scientific claim at all; it is rather a normative epistemological claim, and a quixotic one at that…It is scientific hypotheses which (for the most part) ought to be accepted in the way Worrall celebrates; but of course not nearly all of our beliefs are scientific hypotheses. In particular, religious beliefs are not.[43]

Q13: What for Plantinga is the supposed source of religious knowledge? Does he imagine human beings to posses a unique faculty for acquiring religious knowledge? If so, what are the conditions under which beliefs formed via this faculty is justified?




[1] Pp. 96-97.
[2] P. 102.
[3] P. 104.
[4] Pp. 105-106.
[5] See Job 37:5 (“he does great things beyond our understanding”), Isaiah 45:9 (“woe to those who quarrel with their maker”), Rom. 9:21 ("Shall what is formed say to the one who formed it, 'Why did you make me like this?'"); contrast with 1 Cor. 2:16 (“we have the mind of Christ”), Rom. 12:2 (“that we may discern God’s good, perfect, and pleasing will”), etc.
[6] P. 103.
[7] Pp. 106-107.
[8] Pp. 107-108.
[9] Consider, for example, how many books in ethics and practical reasoning with titles like “Judgment under uncertainty,” or “Who Knew? Responsibility without Awareness.”
[10] P. 108.
[11] P. 102.
[12] P. 103.
[13] P. 109.
[14] Pp. 109-110.
[15] P. 110.
[16] P. 111.
[17] P. 112.
[18] P. 113.
[19] P. 113.
[20] P. 114.
[21] P. 114.
[22] P. 115.
[23] P. 115.
[24] P. 116.
[25] P. 116.
[26] P. 116.
[27] P. 117.
[28] P. 117.
[29] P. 118.
[30] P. 118.
[31] P. 119.
[32] P. 120.
[33] Pp. 120-121.
[34] P. 121.
[35] Pp. 121-122.
[36] P. 122.
[37] Pp. 123-124.
[38] P. 124.
[39] P. 124.
[40] P. 125.
[41] P. 126.
[42] P. 127.
[43] Pp. 127-128.