Monday, July 6, 2015

Chapter 10_The Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism

Introduction

Plantinga: My overall thesis: there is superficial conflict but deep concord between science and religion, and superficial concord but deep conflict between naturalism and science.[1]

à This chapter is dedicated to defending the second half of this claim.

I. Superficial Concord

Plantinga: On balance, theism is vastly more hospitable to science than naturalism, a much better home for it. Indeed, it is theism, not naturalism, that deserves to be called “the scientific worldview.”[2]

II. Deep Conflict

Plantinga: [T]here is deep and irremediable conflict between naturalism and evolution – and hence between naturalism and science.[3]

Plantinga: What I will argue is that naturalism is in conflict with evolution, a main pillar of contemporary science. And the conflict in question is not that they can’t both be true (the conflict is not that there is contradiction between them); it is rather that one can’t sensibly accept them both.[4]

III. The Argument

Plantinga: My argument will center on our cognitive faculties: those faculties, or powers, or processes that produce beliefs or knowledge in us. Among these faculties is memory, whereby we know something of our past. There is also perception, whereby we know something about our physical environment – for the most part our immediate environment, but also something about distant objects such as the sun, the moon, and stars. Another is what is often called “a priori intuition,” by virtue of which we know truths of elementary arithmetic and logic.[5]

Plantinga also recognizes other faculties, including:[6]
(1) Sympathy
(2) Introspection
(3) Testimony
(4) Induction
(5) Moral sense
(6) Sensus divinatis (sense of the divine)

Plantinga: My argument will concern the reliability of these cognitive faculties. My memory, for example, is reliable only if it produces mostly true beliefs – if, that is, most of my memorial beliefs are true.[7]

Plantinga: What proportion of my memorial beliefs must be true for my memory to be reliable?

à Of course there is no precise answer; but presumably it would be greater than, say two-thirds.[8]

We can speak of the reliability of a particular faculty – memory, for example – but also of the reliability of the whole battery of our cognitive faculties. And indeed we ordinarily think our faculties are reliable, at any rate when they are functioning properly, when there is no cognitive malfunction or disorder or dysfunction…We also think they are more reliable under some circumstances than others. Visual perception of middle-sized objects…close at hand is more reliable than perception of very small objects, or middle-sized objects at some distance…Beliefs about where I was yesterday are ordinarily more likely to be true than the latest high-powered scientific theories…Now the natural thing to think, from the perspective of theism, is that our faculties are indeed for the most part reliable, at least over a large part of their range of operations. According to theistic religion (see chapter 9), God has created us in his image; an important part of this image consists in our resembling God in that like him, we can have knowledge.[9]

This, as we’ve discussed before, is an adaptation of a Cartesian argument, which goes like this:

Descartes writes in the Meditations, “When we say...with respect to the body suffering from dropsy, that it has a disordered nature because it has a dry throat and yet does not need drink, the term 'nature' is here used merely as an extraneous label. However, with respect to the composite, that is, the mind united with this body, what is involved is not a mere label, but a true error of nature, namely that it is thirsty at a time when drink is going to cause it harm. It thus remains to inquire how it is that the goodness of God does not prevent nature, in this sense, from deceiving us” (CSM II, 59). He continues later, “[Notwithstanding] the immense goodness of God, the nature of man as a combination of mind and body is such that it is bound to mislead him from time to time...Yet it is much better that it should mislead him [on the occasion of some sickness] than that it should always mislead when the body is in good health” (CSM II, 61). He continues further with suggestions toward how we may even learn to cope with and correct such errors: “[In] matters regarding the well-being of the body, all of my senses report the truth much more frequently than not. Also, I can almost always make use of more than one sense to investigate the same thing; and in addition, I can use both my memory, which connects present experiences with preceding ones, and my intellect, which has by now examined all the causes of error”  (CSM II, 61). “In the case of our clearest and most careful judgments, however, this kind of explanation would not be possible, for if such judgments were false they could not be corrected by any clearer judgments or by means of any natural faculty. In such cases I simply assert that it is impossible for us to be deceived. Since God is the supreme being, he must also be supremely good and true, and it would therefore be a contradiction that anything should be created by him which positively tends towards falsehood...Hence this faculty must tend towards the truth, at least when we use it correctly (that is, by assenting only to what we clearly and distinctly perceive...)” (CSM II, 102-103).

Q1: How important do you think it is that God, assuming he created us, created us with cognitive faculties that are reliable in Plantinga’s sense, i.e., as yielding at least 3 times as many true beliefs as false beliefs? What would be the implications of assuming him to have created us with merely adaptive (rather than materially true) beliefs?

Plantinga: But suppose you are a naturalist: you think that there is no such person as God, and that we and our cognitive faculties have been cobbled together by natural selection. Can you then sensibly think that our cognitive faculties are for the most part reliable?[10]

à I say you can’t. The basic idea of my argument could be put (a bit crudely) as follows. First, the probability of our cognitive faculties being reliable, given naturalism and evolution, is low…But then according to the second premise of my argument, if I believe both naturalism and evolution, I have a defeater for my intuitive assumption that my cognitive faculties are reliable. If I have a defeater for that belief, however, then I have a defeater for any belief I take to be produced by my cognitive faculties. That means that I have a defeater for my belief that naturalism and evolution are true. So my belief that naturalism and evolution are true gives me a defeater for that very belief; that belief shoots itself in the foot and is self-referentially incoherent; therefore, I cannot rationally accept it. And if one can’t accept both naturalism and evolution, that pillar of current science, then there is serious conflict between naturalism and science.[11]

Plantinga: [From  naturalist perspective,] what evolution guarantees is (at most) that we behave in certain ways – in such ways as to promote survival, or more exactly reproductive success. The principal function or purpose, then, (the “chore” says Churchland) of our cognitive faculties is not that of producing true of verisimilitudinous (nearly true) beliefs, but instead that of contributing to survival by getting the body parts in the right place. What evolution underwrites is only (at most) that our behavior is reasonably adaptive to the circumstances in which our ancestors found themselves; hence it does not guarantee mostly true or verisimilitudinous beliefs…What Churchland therefore suggests is that naturalistic evolution…gives us reason to doubt two things: (a) that a purpose of our cognitive systems is that of serving us with true beliefs, and (b) that they do, in fact, furnish us with mostly true beliefs.[12]

Q2: Let’s grant that the naturalist has no reason to believe that his faculties are reliable in Plantinga’s sense, i.e., as yielding at least 3 times as many true beliefs as false beliefs. Assume he is required to replace this premise with the premise that his faculties are reliable only in the sense of generating beliefs that are adaptive. What follows? What should be the naturalist’s attitude toward N&E? Should he believe it? Why or why not? If he did, would his belief be rational? Why or why not?

Recall that, for the naturalist, belief must be given a different analysis than Plantinga has used, too. Belief for the naturalist is presumably not to be taken as the correspondence theory construes it; it may just denote some sort of adequacy for all associated practical functions, as James analyzes it.

James’ Pragmatic Conception of Truth –

The true’, to put it very briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as ‘the right’ is only the expedient in the way of our behaving. Expedient in almost any fashion; and expedient in the long run and on the whole, of course. (1907: 106)

Ideas … become true just in so far as they help us to get into satisfactory relations with other parts of our experience. (1907: 34)

Any idea upon which we can ride …; any idea that will carry us prosperously from any one part of our experience to any other part, linking things satisfactorily, working securely, saving labor; is true for just so much, true in so far forth, true instrumentally. (1907: 34)

Q3: On James’ “pragmatic conception of truth,” and a corresponding analysis of belief (perhaps Schellenberg’s below?) and reliability, would the naturalist still be irrational in “believing” N&E? Why or why not?

Schellenberg’s Account of Acceptance –

The basic distinction here between acceptance and belief I take over from L. Jonathan Cohen’s marvelous little treatise on the subject, though on details I differ with him.[13] The fundamental idea is that acceptance is voluntary while belief is not. To accept that p is to, as a matter of policy, employ that proposition as a premise in relevant reasoning, whereas believing that p is or includes an involuntary disposition to (as one might say) be appeared to p-ly.[14]

Here we see one of the clear differences between propositional faith and propositional belief. When I have faith, I consciously and deliberately don a pair of glasses that give everything – or at least the relevant things – a certain hue (and it may be difficult to keep the glasses on). I know that it is the glasses that produce this effect, while not denying that it might match what I would see without glasses if my vision were sufficiently penetrating. The experience of belief, on the other hand, is like wearing the glasses without knowing it (and here, of course, there can be no associated difficulty, for the representation is not voluntarily produced).[15]

Q4: If the naturalist “accepts” rather than “believes” N&E, can he avoid the irrationality charge? Why or why not?

Q5: Should we even accept Plantinga’s claim that evolutionary theory provides us with no reason to think that our cognitive faculties are reliable (i.e., yield mostly true beliefs)? How might we evaluate this claim? What criteria might we use in order to determine if a particular trait is to be expected given evolutionary theory?

IV. The First Premise: Darwin’s Doubt

Darwin’s doubt – The conditional probability of one proposition p on another proposition q is the probability that p is true given that, on the condition that, q is true…[T]he conditional probability that our cognitive faculties are reliable, given naturalism together with the proposition that we have come to be by way of evolution, is low.

(1) P(R/N&E) is low[16]

Q6: Do you think there’s a way around premise (1)? If so, what are some possible solutions?

Weaker EAN

[In this chapter,] we are speaking of all our cognitive faculties. But perhaps there are interesting distinctions to be made among them. Perhaps some are less likely than others to be reliable, given N&E. perhaps those faculties that produce beliefs that appear to be relevant to survival and reproduction are more likely to be reliable than those faculties that produce beliefs of other kinds. For example, one might think that perceptual beliefs are often more likely to be relevant to adaptive behavior than beliefs about, say, art criticism, or postmodernism, or string theory.[17]

Adjusting the argument to accommodate the considerations above, we might reformulate (1) as follows:

(1*) P(MR/N&E) is low[18]

But, argues Plantinga, since N is a presumably a metaphysical belief, which is only weakly (if at all) relevant to our survival and reproduction, the argument yields the same result.

Plantinga’s Chief Criterion for Reliability – Those faculties that produce beliefs that appear to be relevant to survival and reproduction are more likely to be reliable than those faculties that produce beliefs of other kinds.

Q7: Why might the criterion identified by Plantinga not be the most relevant criterion in judging how likely it is that a particular faculty be reliable? What other criteria might be more relevant to the question of whether a particular faculty is likely to be reliable?

A. Naturalism and Materialism

In this section, Plantinga argues that we should interpret naturalism as entailing materialism about human beings.[19]

Q8: Do you agree that naturalism does, or should, entail materialism about human beings? Why or why not?

B. Beliefs as Neural Structures

Plantinga: Now what sort of thing will a belief be, from this materialist perspective?

à [I]t would have to be something like a long-standing event or structure in your brain or nervous system. Presumably this event will involve many neurons connected to each other in various ways…So (from the naturalist’s point of view) a belief will be a neuronal event or structure of this sort, with input from other parts of the nervous system and output to still other parts as well as to muscles and glands. But if this is the sort of thing beliefs are…they will have two quite different sorts of properties. On the one hand they will have electro-chemical or neurophysiological properties (NP properties, for short)…But if the event in question is really a belief, then in addition to those NP properties it will have another property as well: it will have a content. It will be the belief that p, for some proposition p.[20]

Plantinga: It is in virtue of having content that a belief is true or false: it is true if the proposition which is its content is true, and false otherwise.[21]

Q9: Do you satisfied with Plantinga’s construal of the materialist analysis of belief? Why or why not?

Cosmides’ and Tooby’s Notion of Architectural Truth

We believe that there are a large number of design innovations that have evolved to solve the specialized programming problems posed by using local and contingent information, including a specialized scope syntax, metarepresentational adaptations, and decoupling systems. Indeed, we think that the human cognitive architecture is full of interlocking design features whose function is to solve problems of scope and accuracy. Examples include truth-value tags, source-tags (self vs. other; vision vs. memory, etc.), scope-tags, time and place tags, reference-tags, credal values, operators embodying propositional attitudes, content-based routing of information to targeted inference engines, dissociations, systems of information encapsulation and interaction, independent representational formats for different ontologies, and the architecture and differential volatility of different memory systems. One critical feature is the capacity to carry out inferential operations on sets of inferences that incorporate suppositions or propositions of conditionally unevaluated truth value, while keeping their computational products isolated from other knowledge stores until the truth or utility of the suppositions is decided, and the outputs are either integrated or discarded. This capacity is essential to planning, interpreting, communicating, employing the information communication brings, evaluating others' claims, mind-reading, pretense, detecting or perpetrating deception, using inference to triangulate information about past or hidden causal relations, and much else that makes the human mind so distinctive.
In what follows, we will try to sketch out some of the basic elements of a scope syntax designed to defuse problems intrinsic to the human mode of intelligence. By a scope syntax, we mean a system of procedures, operators, relationships, and data handling formats that regulate the migration of information among subcomponents of the human cognitive architecture.
…To clarify what we mean, consider a simple cognitive system that we suspect is the ancestral condition for all animal minds, and the default condition for the human mind as well: naïve realism. For the naïve realist, the world as it is mentally represented is taken for the world as it really is, and no distinction is drawn between the two. Indeed, only a subset of possible architectures are even capable of representing this distinction, and in the origin and initial evolution of representational systems, such a distinction would be functionless. From our external perspective, we can say of such basic architectures that all information found inside the system is assumed to be true, or is treated as true. However, from the point of view of the architecture itself, that would not be correct, for it would imply that the system is capable of drawing the distinction between true and false, and is categorizing the information as true. Instead, mechanisms in the architecture simply use the information found inside the system to regulate behavior and to carry out further computations. Whatever information is present in the system simply is "reality" for the architecture. Instead of tagging information as true or false - as seems so obvious to us - such basic architectures would not be designed to store false information. When new information is produced that renders old information obsolete, the old information is updated, overwritten, forgotten, or discarded. None of these operations require the tagging of information as true or false. They only involve the rule-governed replacement of some data by other data, just like overwriting a memory register in a personal computer does not require the data previously in that register be categorized as false. For most of the behavior-regulatory operations that representational systems evolved to orchestrate, there would be no point to storing false information, or information tagged as false. For this reason, there is no need in such an architecture to be able to represent that some information is true: its presence, or the decision to store it or remember it, is the cue to its reliability. In such a design, true equals accessible.

With this as background, and leaving aside the many controversies in epistemology over how to conceptualize what truth "really" is, we can define what we will call architectural truth: information is treated by an architecture as true when it is allowed to migrate (or be reproduced) in an unrestricted or scope-free fashion throughout an architecture, and is allowed to interact with any other data in the system that it is capable of interacting with. All data in semantic memory, for example, is architecturally true. The simplest and most economical way to engineer data use is for "true" information to be unmarked, and for unmarked information to be given whatever freedom of movement is possible by the computational architecture. Indeed, any system that acquires, stores, and uses information is a design of this kind. The alternative design, in which each piece of information intended to be used must be paired with another piece of information indicating that the first piece is true, seems unnecessarily costly and cumbersome. Because the true-is-unmarked system is the natural way for an evolved computational system to originate, and because there are many reasons to maintain this system for most uses, we might expect that this is also the reason why humans, and undoubtedly other organisms, are naïve realists. Naïve realism seems to be the likely starting point phylogenetically and ontogenetically, as well as the default mode for most systems, even in adulthood.

Plantinga: Given materialism, therefore, beliefs are (ordinarily) long-standing neural events. As such, they have NP properties, but also content properties…NP properties are physical properties; on the other hand, content properties…are mental properties. Now how, according to materialism, are mental and physical properties related? In particular, how are content properties related to NP properties – how is the content property of a particular belief related to the NP properties of that belief?[22]

Q10: Is something like the mind-body problem inherent to every theory of mind, i.e., to materialism as well as to dualism? Is the materialist’s problem of explaining how physical structures or events give rise to mental events as serious as the dualist’s problem of explaining how immaterial substance causally interacts with physical substance?

Schellenberg’s Account of Belief –

From the fact that my belief is expressed propositionally it does not follow that when I believe, I have a proposition before my mind and am directing some sort of affirming attitude toward that. And when we look carefully at what is actually going on in conscious belief, we can observe that this is in any case false: I am not, one wants to say, thinking of a proposition and under the impression that it is true; rather, I am thinking of a state of affairs and under the impression that it obtains…[O]ne can think of a state of affairs without believing. What is the “certain characteristic way” of having such a thought which brings us all the way to belief?...[T]he believer, when it comes right down to it, is simply thinking of the world. (Notice that the world is real by definition; thus if the world is thought of by someone, there is no way for the question to arise whether he is not after all thinking of things in a detached way, perhaps in imaginative reveries, and thus in a manner implying or consistent with nonbelief.)…It is striking that what the experience of believing really comes down to is simply thinking of the world – no mention of property attribution or of assent or of an extra feeling component that so many (following Hume) have sought to put their finger on will seem tempting to the analyst, once it is seen that correctly identifying the object of the believing thought gives us everything we need. That elusive “characteristic way” in which the believer is supposed to be related to the object of her belief is nothing but a reflection of the object itself.[23]

A belief in p is a disposition to “feel it true” that p.[24]

C. Reductive and Nonreductive Materialism

Reductive materialism – Mental content properties are reducible to NP properties.[25]

Nonreductive materialism – Content properties are not reducible to NP properties, but are determined by (supervene on) NP properties.[26]

So-called eliminative materialists, or eliminativists (like the Churchlands), reject the idea that such things as beliefs, desires, etc. really exist, at least as commonly conceived. They suggest instead that they are folk concepts that will eventually be replaced once science has determined the actual physical structures and processes that underlie them.

Modern versions of eliminative materialism claim that our common-sense understanding of psychological states and processes is deeply mistaken and that some or all of our ordinary notions of mental states will have no home, at any level of analysis, in a sophisticated and accurate account of the mind. In other words, it is the view that certain common-sense mental states, such as beliefs and desires, do not exist.[27]

Plantinga: [W]hat is the likelihood, given evolution and naturalism (construed as including materialism about human beings), that the content thus arising is in fact true? In particular, what is the likelihood, given N&E, that the content associated with our neural structures is true? What is the likelihood, given N&E, that our cognitive faculties are reliable, thereby producing mostly true beliefs?[28]

à Very low.

Q11: Should naturalists accept Plantinga’s framing of the problem? Neither Plantinga’s account of reliability nor his account of truth are very amenable to naturalism, so shouldn’t any argument intended to draw absurd implications from the naturalist view incorporate accounts of reliability and truth that are actually amenable to that view? Is Plantinga’s problem even susceptible to a naturalist-friendly formulation, or does the problem disappear entirely when framed in purely naturalistic terms?

Q12: Does contemporary epistemology already preclude (particularly reductive) materialist analyses? In other words, do you think that contemporary epistemology provides the conceptual and terminological resources it needs to address the most important epistemological questions in a thoroughly reductive materialist way?

V. The Argument for Premise (1)

A. The Argument and Nonreductive Materialism

Plantinga: The NP properties are selected…not because they cause the content they do, but because they cause adaptive behavior.

Objection – consider a frog on a lily pad. A fly buzzes by; the frog’s tongue flicks out and captures the fly. If this frog is to behave successfully, adaptively, there must be mechanisms in it that register the distance to the fly at each moment, its size, speed, and direction, and so on. Aren’t these mechanisms part of the frog’s cognitive faculties? And don’t they have to be accurate in order for the frog to behave adaptively? And isn’t it therefore the case that the frog’s cognitive mechanisms must be accurate, reliable, if the frog is to survive and reproduce?[29]

à Plantinga: [T]hat frog clearly does have “indicators,” neural structures that receive input from the frog’s sense organs, are correlated with the path of the insect as it flies past, and are connected with the frog’s muscles in such a way that it flicks out its tongue and captures that unfortunately fly…[But] indication of this sort does not require belief. In particular, it does not require belief having to do with the state of affairs indicated; indeed it is entirely compatible with belief inconsistent with that state of affairs.[30]

Fleeing predators, finding food and mates – these things require cognitive devices that in some way track crucial features of the environment, and are appropriately connected with muscles; but they do not require true belief, or even belief at all. The long-term survival of organisms of a certain species certainly makes it likely that its members enjoy cognitive devices that are successful in tracking those features of the environment – indicators, as I’ve been calling them. Indicators, however, need not be or involve beliefs.[31]

Indication is one thing; belief content is something else altogether, and we know of no reason (given materialism) why the one should follow the other. We know of no reason why the content of a belief should match what the belief (together, perhaps, with other structures) indicates. Content simply arises upon the appearance of neural structures of sufficient complexity; there is no reason why that content need be related to what the structures indicates, if anything. Indeed, the proposition constituting that content need not be so much as about that predator; it certainly need not be true.[32]

Q13: Is it true that “we know of no reason why the content of a belief should match what the belief indicates” (emphasis mine)?[33] What about our knowledge of what our ancestral environment was like? Or our knowledge how natural selection works? Do either of these provide us with reasons to think that the content of a belief might match what the belief indicates (e.g., by suggesting certain criteria by which the likelihood of a particular trait evolving might be)?

To say that indication of this sort does not require belief does not imply that any other alternative (e.g., one in which content is entirely excluded, or in which the belief is inconsistent with the state of affairs) is equally likely, i.e., given N&E. It may very well be – and perhaps evolutionary theory even predicts this – that the indication function is most likely to have evolved and/or function successfully on a design plan that incorporates a reliable (truth-aimed) faculty.

Q14: Do you think that it is plausible to suppose, as Plantinga seems to, that any of the alternative design plans mentioned above is equally likely to evolve given N&E? Why or why not?

Q15: How might we get adaptive behavior without, or independently of the facilitation provided by, (mechanisms or faculties that produce) true content?

Plantinga: The fact that these creatures have survived and evolved, that their cognitive equipment was good enough to enable their ancestors to survive and reproduce – that fact would tell us nothing at all about the truth of their beliefs or the reliability of their cognitive faculties...[the content of their beliefs] might be true, but might with equal probability be false. So shouldn’t we suppose that the proposition in question has a probability of roughly .5?...That would seem the sensible course. Neither seems more probable than the other; hence we should estimate the probability of its being true as .5…The probability we are thinking of it objective, not the personalist’s subjective probability, and also not epistemic probability.[34]

Plantinga: If I have 1,000 independent beliefs, for example, the probability (under these conditions) that three quarters or more of these beliefs are true will be less than 10-58….So the chances that this creature’s true beliefs substantially outnumber its false beliefs are small. The conclusion to be drawn is that it is very unlikely that the cognitive faculties of those creatures are reliable. [35]

Q16: Why think that these probabilities are equal? Why think that they represent objective probabilities rather than subjective, or epistemic probabilities? How might someone go about calculating these probabilities?

B. The Argument and Reductive Materialism

…(Nothing much to say here)

C. Objection

Objection: Isn’t it just obvious that true beliefs will facilitate adaptive action? A gazelle who mistakenly believes that lions are friendly, overgrown house cats won’t be long for this world…Isn’t it obvious, more generally, that true beliefs are more likely to be successful than false beliefs?[36]

à Yes, certainly. This is indeed true. But it is also irrelevant. We are not asking about how things are, but about what things would be like if evolution and naturalism (construed as including materialism) were true…The question is what things would be like if N&E were true; and in this context we can’t just assume, of course, that if N&E, N including materialism, were true, then thing would still be the way they are. That is, we can’t assume that if materialism were true, it would still be the case that true beliefs are more likely to cause successful action than false beliefs. And in fact, if materialism were true, it would be unlikely that true beliefs mostly cause successful action and false belief unsuccessful action.[37]

Objection: Why think a thing like that? What has materialism got to do with the question?

à Here’s what. We ordinarily think true belief leads to successful action because we also think that beliefs cause (part-cause) actions, and do so by virtue of their content…But now suppose materialism were true: then, as we’ve seen, my belief will be a neural structure that has both NP properties and also a propositional content. It is by virtue of the NP properties, however, not the content, that the belief causes what it does cause. It is by virtue of those properties that the belief causes neural impulses to travel down the relevant efferent nerves to the relevant muscles causing them to contract, and thus causing behavior. It isn’t by virtue of the content of this belief; the content of the belief is irrelevant to the causal power of the belief with respect to the behavior.[38]

Q17: How is it, on the nonreductive materialist account that Plantinga is using to frame this problem, that the content of the belief is supposed to be “irrelevant to the causal power of the belief with respect to the behavior”? Is Plantinga imagining the truth of the content of the NPs to be accidental to their functioning in this capacity? How would that work structurally? If this were the case, why should NP properties ever have evolved the ability to determine content properties (much less, content properties that are true)?

Objection: You claim that
(1) If the belief B had had the same NP properties but different content, it still would have had the same causal effects with respect to behavior;

But it couldn’t have had the same NP properties but different content. (1) is not merely counterfactual; it’s counterpossible.[39]

à Plantinga: [Usual semantics for counterfactual notwithstanding, the] truth of (1) gives us some reason to think that B doesn’t cause that action A by virtue of its content…It is [rather] by virtue of its neurological properties that B causes A; it is by virtue of those properties that B sends a signal along the relevant nerves to the relevant muscles, causing them to contract, and thus causing A. It isn’t by virtue of its having that particular content C that it causes what it does cause.[40]

Q18: What do you think of Plantinga’s response to the objection above?

VI. The Remaining Premises

Plantinga: [T]he naturalist who sees that P(R/N&E) is low has a defeater for R, and for the proposition that his own cognitive faculties are reliable. A defeater for a belief B I hold – at any rate this kind of defeater – is another belief B* I come to hold which is such that, given that I hold B*, I can no longer rationally hold B.[41]

(2) Anyone who accepts (believes) N&E and sees that (P/R N&E) is low has a defeater for R.[42]

Plantinga: It isn’t that someone who believes N&E wouldn’t have enough evidence for R to believe it rationally. The fact is I don’t need evidence for R. That’s a good thing, because it isn’t possible to acquire evidence for T, at least if I have any doubts about it.[43]

Q19: Why isn’t it possible to acquire evidence for R? What does having doubts about R have to do with the impossibility of acquiring evidence?

à Plantinga: My accepting any argument for R, or any evidence for it, would clearly presuppose my believing R; any such procedure would therefore be viciously circular.[44]

Objection: Why should we think that premise (2) is true? Some propositions of that form are true, but some aren’t.

à Plantinga: Right: not every proposition of that form is true. This one is, however. What’s at issue, I think, is the question what else I believe (more exactly what else is such that I believe it and can legitimately conditionalize on it in this context).[45]

Plantinga: But now think about N&E and R. We agree that P(R/N&E) is low. Do I know something else, in addition to N&E, such that (a) I can properly conditionalize on X, and (b) P(R/N&E&X) is high? This is the conditionalization problem, which I address briefly on pages [357-358].[46]

(3) Anyone who has a defeater for R has a defeater for any other belief she thinks she has, including N&E itself.[47]

Q20: Might not the apparent fact that our beliefs lead us into reasonably fruitful interactions with the world provide us with a reason to believe that, despite Plantinga’s concerns, our faculties are nonetheless reliable, at least in relevant sense? In other words, is a Kantian defense of the reliability of our faculties, grounded in their practical efficacy, possible here?

Q21: How about the possibility that the truth of certain beliefs, e.g., those in the elementary arithmetic and logic, is self-evident? Is it even possible to seriously doubt the reliability of the faculty(/ies) that produces these beliefs? If not, does this knowledge raise the probability of R(N&E)?

(4) If one accepts N&E thereby acquires a defeater for N&E, N&E is self-defeating and can’t rationally be accepted.

Plantinga: Is there any sensible way at all in which [someone] can argue for R?

à It is hard to see how. Any argument she might produce will have premises; these premises, she claims, give her good reasons to believe R. But of course she has the very same defeater for each of those premises that she has for R, and she has the same defeater for the belief that if the premises of that argument are true, then so is the conclusion…This defeater, therefore, can’t be defeated. Hence the devotee of N&E has an undefeated defeater for N&E.[48]

Summary
(1) P(R/N&E) is low
(2) Anyone who accepts (believes) N&E and sees that (P/R N&E) is low has a defeater for R.
(3) Anyone who has a defeater for R has a defeater for any other belief she thinks she has, including N&E itself.
(4) If one accepts N&E thereby acquires a defeater for N&E, N&E is self-defeating and can’t rationally be accepted.
à Conclusion: N&E can’t be rationally accepted.

What Plantinga’s argument amounts to is a rejection of a non-theistic foundational epistemology. He is basically reaffirming Descartes’ thesis that the only possible foundation for justifying our claims of possessing knowledge, whether empirical or a priori, is an assurance (or perhaps simply assumption) of God’s existence.

Q22: Assuming that the naturalist even cares to safeguard his claim to possess knowledge, what foundation besides the assumption that his faculties are reliable might be available to him? Is it evolutionary theory that generates this problem? Is there another account besides either evolution or divine creation that might still serve to safeguard our claims to possess knowledge?

VII. Two Concluding Comments

Plantinga: The naturalist might have a defeater deflector, i.e., a belief that together with N&E serves to raise the probability of R to high…[I]s there are a defeater deflector for the defeat of R threatened by N&E and P(R/N&E) is low?

à Well, it certainly looks as if there are: what about R itself? That’s presumably something the naturalist believes…But of course R itself isn’t a proper candidate for being a defeater deflector here. If a belief A could itself be a defeater-deflector for a putative defeater of A, no belief could ever be defeated.[49]


[1] P. 317.
[2] P. 319.
[3] P. 319-320.
[4] P. 320.
[5] p. 321-322.
[6] P. 322.
[7] P. 322.
[8] P. 323.
[9] P. 322-323.
[10] P. 323.
[11] P. 324.
[12] P. 325-326.
[13] See L. Jonathan Cohen, An Essay on Belief and Acceptance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992). My understanding of acceptance is in some ways closer to that of Gregory W. Dawes in “Belief is not the Issue: A Defense of Inference to the Best Explanation,” Ratio 26 (2013), 62-78.
[15] Schellenberg, J.L. Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion, 134.
[16] P. 327.
[17] P. 359.
[18] P. 360.
[19] P. 330.
[20] P. 331.
[21] P. 332.
[22] P. 332.
[23] Schellenberg, J.L. Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion, 47.
[24] Schellenberg, J.L. Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason, 30.
[25] P. 333.
[26] P. 333.
[28] P. 335.
[29] P. 337-338.
[30] P. 338.
[31] P. 339.
[32] P. 341.
[33] Consider also the alternatives to this formulation discussed above. On Schellenberg’s account, Plantinga would have to say (roughly) that “we know of no reason why the subjective representation of an object should match the object as it objectively is.” But this formulation doesn’t seem nearly as strong as the one he puts forward.
[34] P. 341.
[35] P. 343.
[36] P. 345.
[37] P. 345-346.
[38] P. 346.
[39] P. 347-348.
[40] P. 349.
[41] P. 350.
[42] P. 351.
[43] P. 351.
[44] P. 351.
[45] P. 353.
[46] P. 354.
[47] P. 354.
[48] P. 356.
[49] P. 357.