Friday, October 11, 2013

Preface: Where the Conflict Really Lies (Comments continued)

Before I publish the full 17 pages of this response, let me just offer a brief disclaimer. Most of the things I talk about below are far, far afield of our primary topic of discussion, and probably don’t really belong here at all. However, since Colby and I have been the only regular participants up to this point, and my response addresses some questions that apparently are of interest to him, I decided to go ahead and include it just as one huge side note to this section’s discussion. To anyone else who might join our discussion later, I apologize for getting so far off topic. Feel free to voice your complaints if we start to do it again.

Q2C –

Colby wrote,

…if people are going to take a hard stance on something, especially if it has as much significance as the existence of God, they should be able to do so with strong, substantive evidence on their side.

When you say “take a hard stance,” do you mean epistemically or practically? Taking a hard stance on something epistemically might mean something like claiming knowledge or strong certainty about a subject, while taking a hard stance on something practically might simply mean being committed to a certain pattern of behavior, or to living as if something were true (even though you might not be at all certain of it). I think this distinction is an important one, because agnosticism doesn’t necessarily entail practical ambivalence, or vice-versa, and most people, I think, would say that morality often demands a practical resoluteness disproportionate to our epistemic certainty. Consider the following example.

In late 1993, the Criminal Division of the Washington State Attorney General's Office undertook a 3-1/2 year research project, partially funded by the U.S. Department of Justice, Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention, to study the investigation of child abduction murder cases…In 76 percent of the missing children homicide cases studied, the child was dead within three hours of the abduction–and in 88.5 percent of the cases the child was dead within 24 hours.[1]

Given these facts, how should we expect parents to behave whose child has recently gone missing? If we were to straightforwardly apply the rule you proposed and, in situations in which something significant was at stake, only take our stand with strong, substantive evidence on our side, then we should expect the parents to give up their search within the first 3 hours. But that’s not what we expect of the parents of kidnapped children, Why? Presumably, because we don’t intuitively approve of proportioning one’s belief – or certainly not one’s actions – to the evidence: extra-evidential considerations, like in what direction our practical interests lie, also matter. In fact, it would seem a more accurate description of our moral intuitions to say that the more significant the stakes of our decisions are, the less important it is to have strong, substantive evidence on our side.

That being said, I think you’re right that we run a pretty significant risk when we attempt to bolster one or another practical agenda on a presumption of superior evidence or arguments, if in fact that evidence doesn’t exist or those arguments aren’t as strong as we’ve made them out to be. That risk is just that people might eventually become so accustomed to rehearsing these arguments and evidences as the prime justification of their practical commitments that they eventually come to forget all the other, non-evidential reasons for which they made those commitments in the first place. This reliance may in time grow so complete that, were those arguments and evidences to ever fail, certain individuals might subsequently feel obliged to abandon their practical commitments, and perhaps end up with an ultimately less desirable or satisfying life.

I think the preferred way to avoid this problem is not to obsess over one’s evidences and arguments until one is perfectly confident that all of one’s practical commitments can be defended on rational or evidential grounds alone, but rather to never fall under the impression that evidence and arguments are what our practical commitments are all about in the first place. As many moral philosophers have pointed out, our practical commitments – especially of the moral variety – reflect not so much our beliefs about how the world is, but rather our vision of what our actions might potentially make it.[2] Likewise, our justification for living a certain way – our entitlement to the life that we love, and which is in harmony with our cares and interests – is grounded not in the evidence that proves that our hopes will be realized, but in the vast superiority of the future that our efforts strive to realize over that which would be left to us were we to resign them.

Colby wrote:

…it is my view that either side would be far more effective in the long run to teach people substantive arguments that hold up to scrutiny rather than just appealing to emotion and sensationalism…

I agree that this is the most intuitive view, but, following what I said above, I think there are some really good, less-obvious considerations in favor of the latter view, which a slight change in perspective about what it is exactly that these apologists and popular religious critics are doing can make more clear. Here’s my reasoning, you can tell me what you think about it:

(1)  When people debate issues with important practical implications, they are not seeking to influence their audience’s beliefs as much as they are trying to influence their behavior. Speculative debates (i.e., debates concerning what the facts are, or what we should believe), in other words, are often just practical debates in disguise (i.e., debates over what we should do, or how far what we know goes in justifying the various practical alternatives). For example, when two people argue about whether or not God exists, what they are often really arguing about is whether the available evidence justifies not the belief or disbelief in God per se, but the behavior that belief or disbelief in God entails. So, in the context of the present debate, the apologists could be interpreted as arguing, in essence, that the atheist doesn’t have adequate evidence to justify living as if God didn’t exist, while the religious critic could be interpreted as arguing, in essence, that the Christian doesn’t have adequate evidence to justify living as if God did exist.
(2)  Behaviors, moreover, are justified on the basis of different criteria than are beliefs. Namely, beliefs are justified primarily on the basis of evidence that either supports or refutes them, while behaviors are justified primarily on the basis of one’s practical interests (or perhaps the collective interests of one’s society, or all mankind). Epistemic norms are oriented to a different value than are moral norms, and often these two systems’ values are in conflict with one another, such that moral norms may actually prescribe actions that epistemic norms would prohibit.[3] While evidentialism provides a good approximation of epistemic normativity, it falls short of describing moral normativity, which actually follows a more Platonic or Jamesian principle, e.g., “believe[/act] in the line of your needs.”[4]
To summarize – Were the question merely about the most appropriate or ethical way to change someone’s mind with respect to some target belief (e.g., whether or not God exists), then I think Colby / Clifford would be right. But since the question is actually, though not explicitly, about the most appropriate or ethical way to change someone’s mind about some target behavior (whether or not we should live as though God existed or did not exist), I actually think it’s Plato’s / James’ prescription that best reflects our moral intuitions.

Q3C –

Colby wrote:

…the point I was making was largely the last part of what you said, that “scientists themselves… exaggerate the finality of their favorite scientific theories.” The scientific community needs to be more honest about this. If you talk about something scientific with people just in conversation or you watch some scientific presentation, as I mentioned, it is unlikely that you will see “facts” presented just as the best information we have now—it is far more likely to be presented as “this is the way it is,” which comes across to the average person as “fact.”

Yeah, it’s an interesting question why science is a field so rife with equivocations of this kind. I guess you could take a sort of quasi-Kantian approach, and argue that the scientific definition of fact (i.e., as something provisional, subject to change) is really the only definition that can possibly have any meaning for “phenomenally-bound” human beings, since the stronger definition (i.e., that which presents a fact as something known, and immune to future revision) represents more of an epistemically inaccessible “noumenal” ideal. So you could say that (capital-F) Fact doesn’t really refer to anything that we phenomenally-bound human beings could ever hope to know anything about, and so we should simply never presume that this definition is what is intended when anyone, scientist or otherwise, uses the word “fact.”

Or you could take more of a contextualist approach and argue that in normal “low stakes” contexts (e.g., common parlance), the criteria for what suffices as a “fact” are more permissive than in “high stakes” contexts (e.g., “brain-in-vat” scenarios). Then you could say that scientists are typically in relatively low stakes contexts when they talk about facts, and so their fact-statements are permissible because the lower-stakes criteria are operative.

Both of those responses, though, involve technical terms and concepts with which most of those reading this blog won’t be familiar. And, anyway, the most likely explanation is just that scientists themselves have trouble making the distinction between the two definitions, or simply get carried away. Long story short, I agree that we should watch our language more carefully.

Colby wrote:

I suppose this may not have been Plantinga’s point, but it seems relevant to his point that science isn’t up to the task. I’ve explained some why I would agree that science may not be up to the task, so what are your thoughts on this now?

If the point is something like "Ccientists themselves often exaggerate the finality of their favorite scientific theories, therefore science isn't up to the task of grounding our beliefs and guiding our actions,” then I don't think I'd agree. It might be unsuitable for other reasons, but not because of the behavior of scientists. I know that’s not quite what you meant, and I doubt it’s what Plantinga meant either, but I think it’s worth saying…

As to whether I personally think science is up to the task of grounding our beliefs and guiding our behaviors, I’m not sure what I’d say. I guess my general conviction is that we don’t so much need facts OR dogma for morality as people are inclined to believe[5], but that between the two of these, facts are much more helpful, and science is much better than religion at providing them.

Q4C/Q5C –

Colby wrote:

…some of these questions are very loaded and I just don’t think they largely fit this particular discussion (and we’re only in the preface!!!).

I admit to stating my case a little more bluntly than usual, but I inserted the appropriate qualifiers (“it wouldn’t seem to be”) so as to leave all possibilities open. Besides, I addressed some of these claims in a much more thorough and charitable fashion in previous posts (see http://muckrunner.blogspot.com/2009/09/moral-dilemma-part-2.html). I appreciate your effort to keep us on task, though : )

Colby wrote:

I don’t know that we need to assume the greater “miracle” is the false one right off the bat. Why would we not weigh all evidence available to us rather than just assume the more difficult view is false?...In simplistic terms, we have two possible ideas regarding the origin of the universe: 1) it was designed intentionally by some being, or 2) it was formed from nothing and evolved to its current state…Having myself observed many of the complexities of the world and having a basic scientific understanding of how the universe works, I consider #2 to be far more miraculous than #1. Am I really to believe the universe did not exist and a “big bang” (what does that even mean?) formed it? From there, should it be obvious to me that the unfathomably complex creatures that we are, with aspects such as DNA, senses, the mind, etc., all formed without intention out of very simple non-sentient building-blocks? In my view, the world looks far more like one that was formed intentionally.

I guess what you take to be the implications of Hume’s principle depends pretty heavily on how you define the term “miraculous.” It sounds to me like you might be thinking of miraculous in terms of difficulty to grasp intuitively or intellectually (?). And, granted, evolution by natural selection, big bangs, and the rest of it, are not the most obvious or intuitive explanations for everything that we observe. But besides the fact that you presumably don’t feel responsible for understanding the mechanism(s) that would enable a God to create this universe, or, for that matter, to even exist in the first place, I don’t see how the theistic perspective provides any simpler an explanation (i.e., to grasp intuitively or intellectually). If you think along the lines of even most theologians, then even assuming the existence of God doesn’t get you around the problem of natural selection and the big bang, because God presumably had to have created the universe via some natural mechanism(s) that matches their general description, adding perhaps the qualification that these process were guided. Unfortunately, this alleged “guidedness” is not something that scientists can observe, or even infer from what is observed, making that feature of the theory (for the moment, at least) explanatorily extraneous. A problem, in other words, for the theologian, is that even if God did design the whole complicated system, he appears to have created it in such a way as to be able to function on its own (i.e., at least after some initial impetus like the big bang, or through infinite cycling), allowing scientists to describe its workings with no reference to God whatsoever: the world with God, for all we can tell, looks just like the world without him. Given that scientists seem to be able to explain the operation of the system without invoking God as part of their explanation, it’s not clear to me how bringing him back into the picture is supposed to make grasping these phenomena intuitively or intellectually more simple. What theoretical work is this divine guidedness supposed to be doing? (Again, not trying to be antagonistic, just asking what I think are the pertinent questions.)

Second, I don’t think that “difficult to grasp intuitively or intellectually” is the definition that Hume had in mind for the term “miraculous” in the first place. I think he meant something more like “contrary to what we typically observe,” or “most dissimilar to our other experiences.” (Hume, by the way, had a much weaker notion of natural law than most of us: he was a skeptic about traditional causes, i.e., of the necessary following of one thing from another via natural law. For Hume, we add something to experience when we presume a law to govern the constant conjunction of two events, since all we ever actually observe is their constant conjunction.) If we interpret Hume in this way, then we don’t have to assume his judgment would be handicapped by something as accidental to the facts as how he happened to perceive them. In other words, even if (a) Hume were in Colby’s shoes instead of his own, and (b) he were applying his rule to judge the probable explanation of the universe rather than the probable explanation for the disciple’s testimony about a resurrected Jesus; and (c) all the available evidence were weighed prior to passing judgment, I think we’re supposed to think that the outcome would be precisely the same.

Anyway, I took your main objection to be this: Why should someone’s subjective evaluation of which of two alternative scenarios is the least miraculous (roughly translated “difficult to grasp intuitively or intellectually”) be considered a reliable method for arriving at the truth of the matter? To which I would respond, I don’t think that’s what Hume meant. I think Hume had a much more objective criterion in mind: “miraculous” is not just what someone finds unintuitive or intellectually difficult, but what is most contrary to what we typically observe, most dissimilar to our other experiences.

But maybe you’d like to reformulate your objection like this: Why should evaluating which of two alternative scenarios is more dissimilar to our other experiences be considered a reliable method for arriving at the truth of the matter? (Maybe, for example, arriving at the truth also requires something like faith in the impossible.) To which I would respond, What better ideas do you have for arriving at the truth of the matter? Or if you have none for arriving at the truth, what better ideas do you have for deciding which of the available alternatives will provide the best foundation for our belief or confidence? Honestly, I think the latter question is much more important than the former, and for our current purposes, much more relevant. In considering the latter question, however, I have to admit that I have genuine difficulty understanding on what grounds Christianity is supposed to achieve its superior credibility over science when in every parameter I consider apart from aesthetic appeal and scope of application, science (in my assessment) clearly surpasses it. What I wrote before I think deserves careful reconsideration:

Whatever evidences or arguments might possibly justify the Christian’s confidence in the infallibility of the Bible, can they possibly amount to as much as all the evidence supporting our confidence in science?...[I]f we could claim on behalf of our religion all the successes that science has secured for us, and if the only disappointments we had to rationalize away were those in which our nutritionists fed us misinformation about what portions of what food group comprised a balanced diet, just imagine how vindicated we’d feel in our faith…The primary advantage that the Bible enjoys over science textbooks, then, in my opinion, is not that it contains more factual content, or that it generates fewer disappointments in our intellectual or practical lives, but rather that it has stronger aesthetic appeal (i.e., it presents a more “intuitive” and emotionally satisfying worldview than that which science is revealing) and lends itself to wider application (i.e., it tells us how we should live in addition to what we should believe).

Colby wrote:

It seems you are assuming that a reliance on scripture is in fact problematic and may even be thinking that a reliance on science is NOT problematic. You seem to suggest the questions you ask do not have answers and that the “proposed mechanism” is therefore more problematic than science—this is not the case. Would [you not] agree that both sides have their share of problems? Fortunately for science, it can get away with just saying “I don’t know”—Christians are not afforded the same luxury in some areas (and rightly so).

If that’s how I came off, that wasn’t my intention. Sometimes the questions I present are intended merely to describe the situation as I see it and help focus our efforts at crafting solutions in the directions that I think are most promising (or most urgently needed). But probably more often I’m just trying to raise the questions that I imagine a critical reader – on either side of the debate – would have if they were to join the discussion. I think that’s kind of the special responsibility of whoever is facilitating the discussion for a particular week: to anticipate and voice the questions, objections, and possible solutions of all sides in the debate. Hopefully as the discussion moves forward, you'll see that I’m just as critical of certain opinions and arguments on the other side of the debate.

But to address your point directly, I don’t think that reliance on science isn’t problematic – I think that reliance on anything is problematic in some way or another. I DO think, however, that reliance on scripture is problematic in much more obvious ways than reliance on science (one of them being lack of clear standards to evaluate competing claims, while science has a verifiability criterion and peer review). Actually, to be fair, I think it might be a toss-up when it comes to having one of them guide our actions (since, as you and Plantinga have both pointed out, science hasn’t had much to say on this topic for most of human history).

I disagree, though, that Christians are not afforded the same luxury as science to admit that they don’t know if in fact they really don’t know. Or are you just saying that part of a Christian’s belief commitments just is the belief that they know certain things, e.g., that God is a certain way, that the Bible is his inspired word, that they will spend eternity in heaven, etc.? If that’s what you’re saying, do you mean to say that Christians don’t have the luxury to say that they don’t know because they actually do know, or that they don’t have this luxury because they don’t know but are supposed to know? Can you explain what you had in mind?

Colby wrote:

At least part of why religious leaders (and scripture) prescribe that we “live by faith” is in fact because there are many things we may never know by empirical data.

Again, this was a sincere question, not an attempt to antagonize, so I appreciate you answering it. I agree with you, that at least part of why religious leaders prescribe living by faith is because there are plenty of things of practical importance about which we will never have empirical evidence (or sufficient empirical evidence, I should probably say). But is that the only value that faith has, i.e., to fill in the gaps left by science? Or are there areas, too, that science does claim to address in which we should nonetheless practice faith, i.e., in spite of science? I don’t know, there seems something strange to me in characterizing faith simply as the “next best thing” to empirical evidence, and I’m just trying to put my finger on what that something is. (Maybe John 20:29, 2 Cor. 5:7, etc.?)

Colby wrote:

You can tell me there is a massive host of reasons that science is considered reliable by means of the reliability of its proponents (i.e., scientists, writers, etc.), and I can say with confidence that the same is true of the scriptures. People have devoted their entire lives to studying different aspects of science, but people have also devoted their entire lives to studying the scriptures in their original languages, studying other historic data from other cultures before, during, and after the Biblical events, doing archaeological digs, etc., verifying the claims of the scripture. How are these two fields different in their reliability?

Good question. I think there might be several reasons to trust the scientific community over the religious community. I’ll admit that I haven’t given it a ton of thought, but these are my initial thoughts for what they’re worth. First of all, there is greater convergence of belief between top experts in the scientific community with respect to the field’s major tenets than there is among biblical scholars, for instance, which are split pretty decisively between conservative and liberal schools. Second, the relatively high degree of convergence we find within the conservative school of biblical scholarship, seems to owe more to the special requirements imposed by that field to first adopt the tenets that it will later critically examine, i.e., to the experts’ membership in an associated religious tradition. (The liberal school seems hardly worth mentioning, since many, if not most, of them don’t even affirm the truth of the book’s content.) Thirdly, the worldview presented by science does not cater as strongly, if at all to the practical, emotional, and aesthetic interests of humans, and therefore provides fewer alternative incentives for adopting or propagating it than does any religious worldview. (This last consideration happens to be the same reason I am more distrustful of dieticians or nutritionists who both prescribe vegetarianism as the optimal diet for human beings as well as have strong feelings about animal rights. It’s not that I necessarily doubt that there are good reasons to adopt each position independently, but I do question whether the emotional incentives surrounding the second issue might be supplanting in some places the empirical evidence in support of the first.) What do you think? Does having a dog in the fight, so to speak, help or hinder our capacity to think critically?

Colby wrote:

Regarding another point you make, the existence of contradictory evidence, I would say that the “empirical evidence” that may contradict the examples you gave would be circumstantial and subjective at best. Can you really say that a prayer not being answered according to how you believe it should be answered is “empirical evidence” that prayer is ineffective or that having not observed a “miracle” yourself means miracles don’t exist? This amounts to “if I don’t see it, it doesn’t exist,” which is of course no argument at all.

You’re right, that wouldn’t be much of an argument. But imagine that two people were making two competing claims about the color of crows. Person A claims that all crows are black, while Person B claims that some crows are white. Both are empirical claims, but Person A’s claim provides a relatively simple route to empirical refutation while Person B’s claim doesn’t (a single white crow would decisively refute Person A’s claim while a hundred zillion black crows would still be insufficient to refute Person B’s claim, since the future may, for all we know, still bring a white crow). The empirical claims of Christianity are either of the first or second sort. If they are of the first sort, then it is not all that unlikely, at least in principle, that certain people might have acquired evidence that decisively refuted it (short of having some independent reason to think that the existence of white crows is impossible, like square circles for instance). If they are of the second sort, however, you’re right that it seems very unlikely, even in principle, that anyone has acquired any decisive evidence to refute it. I guess my question, then, would be: What sort of empirical claims does the Bible contain: the first or second? If this comment was at all unclear, you can find an extended version of the argument here: http://muckrunner.blogspot.com/2013/10/personal-experience-as-defeater-of.html and also here: http://muckrunner.blogspot.com/2013/10/james-on-achieving-intimacy-with-god.html.

Colby wrote:

If I am thoroughly convinced that God exists and that the claims of the Bible are true it would behoove me to live my life in a certain way, in light of this truth, would it not? In the examples you gave about science being more reliable and how it affects our lives, those are highly empirical examples. We act in those ways (boarding a plane, taking a pill, boarding up windows) because we have personally observed the science involved to be true. You cannot really compare this to something like evolution or the origin of the cosmos.

First of all, just to clarify, I’m not suggesting that we attempt to apply our knowledge about the big bang or evolution to the resolution of practical or moral dilemmas, at least in any direct fashion. To say that science has something to say that bears on our practical and moral lives isn’t the same thing as saying that everything that science says bears on our practical and moral lives.

That being said, I think the parallel between faith in science and religious faith is a lot closer than you recognize. Christians believe things about God that far outrun the limited practical engagements they’ve allegedly had with him in precisely the same way as many of us believe things scientists tell us about the universe that far outrun the limited practical engagements we’ve had with science. The difference, in my mind, is that the level to which we’re allowed to engage with science so as to shore up our confidence in its general reliability (the pills that cure our illnesses, the planes that carry us safely to our destination, the chemistry experiments we performed in high school, etc.) is much greater than that to which we’re allowed to engage with God so as to shore up reliability in his general reliability.

It is at a relatively few points of practical convergence that we form our first notions of both science’s as well as God’s reliability in the things that we still have not experienced or confirmed for ourselves. Even so, it would seem curious to me if someone who had once experienced the effectiveness of science to cure a virtually invisible illness, or land an automated motor vehicle on the surface of Mars and later retrieve it, still felt justified in their skepticism that science really knows about human physiology or interplanetary travel. (Apparently they know enough to be effective in this wide range of practical applications, right?) The science behind the things we’ve seen and benefited from isn’t necessarily any more or less sophisticated than the science behind the things we haven’t, so what is it exactly that’s supposed to justify their skepticism?

What is even more curious to me is that the skepticism that Christians so often bring into their engagements with science is largely absent from their religious lives, despite being plagued by the same uncertainty (and arguably much more). Granted, you don’t see many Christians these days marching 300 men out against armies of tens of thousand, but there’s hardly a Christian out there who won’t profess to believing, for instance, that his soul will survive his bodily death – and it’s hard for me to imagine an experience one could possibly have that could support that belief.

So how is it that the same individuals who are willing to stake their eternity on such relatively paltry evidence can simultaneously feel justified in their skepticism toward science, the proofs of which permeate their daily lives? The most likely explanation in my mind, as I’ve suggested before, is that we simply require fewer evidences to justify a belief in a prospect that we find emotionally satisfying or practically useful than we would to justify a belief in a prospect that that rather threatens these interests. As William James puts it, we “believe in the line of our needs.”[6]

Not just Christians, but human beings generally, exhibit strong biases in the way they allocate their trust. My personal opinion is that Christians should spend less time trying to deny that this fact has anything to do with their personal faith, and more time thinking about why we’re inclined in these ways to begin with. Maybe somewhere in that explanation is also a possible justification, one that is not only more honest, but also more compelling than the one they presently rely one.

Colby wrote:

I would also argue that many people can and do claim an experience accurate to what the Bible purports, even if you personally cannot say the same. I wouldn’t say that one person’s experience differing from yours can be attributed to their greater ability to “rationalize away” their disappointments. I don’t consider my own convictions about the truth of scripture to be so un-substantive and unfounded so as to be so easily discarded or explained away in such simplistic terms.

This goes back to the black crow comment from before. I think this is an important point, so I’ll make it again: If everyone else’s experience were to amount to something like a hundred zillion black crows, and mine a single white crow, then my experience would have more direct bearing than all of theirs on the question of whether all crows are black – not because I’m more special or intelligent than they are, but simply because a hundred zillion black crows can’t prove decisively that all crows are black, but one white crow can decisively refute it. I understand Christianity to contain at least some portion of claims similar in form to “all crows are black,” i.e., claims of universal scope, such that one experience that fails to conform to it effectively refutes it. In principle, therefore, I see no problem with someone – myself included – claiming that their personal experiences not simply differ from, but positively refute, the collective experiences of all Christians.

The fact that so many Christians continue to believe would not particularly surprising if the experiences that the Biblical claims discounted (the white crows, so to speak) were sufficiently infrequent or inconspicuous as to avoid detection by the majority of individuals. On that note, it should be clear that we don’t need to assume Christians to be unusually self-deluded or intellectually unscrupulous to explain the fact that so many of them continue to believe what they do. On the contrary, my point is precisely that Christians are not exceptional in any way whatsoever, and neither, necessarily, are those who may believe they’ve refuted Christianity. In principle, someone could arrive at either destination either through blind wandering or deliberate searching (although, depending on how many white crows were really out there, you might have to start wondering a little about how hard those who still insisted all crows were black were really looking.)

Colby wrote:

You may be right that something like scripture does have a more aesthetic appeal, but I don’t think that this means a religion’s adherents are inherently less informed…Most atheists (the “masses” that love Richard Dawkins) are no more informed about their worldview than the average Christian…I believe it is fallacious to say that religions have something that is intrinsically more appealing to the “masses” over an atheistic worldview, which is more rational or evidential—this is not the case. Would you disagree with this?

I agree that the average atheist is probably equally uninformed about his/her own beliefs as is the average Christian. I disagree, though, that the two worldviews have equal aesthetic and emotional appeal, or exert an equivalent influence over our beliefs: the religious worldview enjoys a significant advantage on both fronts, I think. This is an empirical question, though, so no use in arguing about it without the relevant data in front of us.

Q6C & Q7C – 




Colby wrote:

How do you measure “happiness?” It cannot be objectively measured. This is, of course, the fundamental flaw of Utilitarianism.

First of all, why think that happiness can’t be objectively measured? It’s not absurd to think that certain neurotransmitters like endorphins, serotonin, dopamine, and oxytocin might one day be measured as proxies for happiness. We already actively manipulate people’s emotions through chemical intervention, so why shouldn’t we also be able to measure these same chemicals to provide information about people’s present emotional state?

Second of all, even if happiness itself is an objective matter, why insist on measuring happiness via objective means? People’s subjective self-reports might also provide some meaningful insight into what makes people objectively happy. I happen to have three different clinical tests alleging to measure happiness in my notebook as we speak, one of which makes use of a “Subjective Happiness Scale” (SHS).[7] Meanwhile, the United Nation’s Sustainable Development Solutions Network apparently feels confident enough in the meaningfulness of subjective self-reports as to rank the various countries of the world according to how happy they are, and declare one of them “Happiest Country on Earth” (fyi, last year Denmark won the prize).[8] The small country of Bhutan in South Asia even has a Gross National Happiness (GNH) index alongside that used to measure Gross Domestic Product (GDP).[9]

Colby wrote:

Even if it were possible to measure “happiness,” this is in and of itself subjective. To the sociopath or psychopath, there may be an extreme level of happiness associated with killing another person or with even reducing the happiness of another person. Each person may derive a certain level of pleasure from different actions, which can never be measured objectively.

Actually, from what I understand, the actions of psychopaths are better explained with reference to (1) their lack of capacity for empathy, coupled with (2) a non-functioning fear response, which would otherwise make them averse to violent or gruesome actions, as well as to the consequences of those actions (which they seem either unable to anticipate, or undeterred by). In other words, they don’t do those things because it makes them happy. In fact, I think I read that psychopaths lack a robust emotional life altogether (something wrong with their limbic brain, I think), which may simply count them out from moral consideration altogether (or at least equal moral consideration, since their capacity for happiness would presumably be lower than the average person). So we may be able to just sidestep this problem altogether: sociopaths are either incapable of genuine happiness (0 points), or their happiness doesn’t explain the unpleasant things they do (in which case, forbidding them to do those things wouldn’t negatively affect their happiness). If it were happiness that was at issue, however, then maybe what is best (i.e., morally right) for the rest of us is simply to disassociate ourselves from psychopaths, e.g., isolate them in mental care facilities, or even eradicate them. Sounds cruel, I know, but hey…

Colby wrote:

It is not possible to determine all possible outcomes and therefore the total level of happiness resulting from one action or another. This would require seeing and knowing the future, or having some advanced technology (as you mention), which will never exist.

You’re right that predictions regarding which of a variety of alternative choices will maximize total happiness are problematic: Utilitarianism (and interest-based ethical theories generally) provides a much more effective tool for evaluating choices already made than it does prescribing what future course of action to take. But even when we have no certain answer, there are still better and worse guesses. The account I proposed merely claims that we are most likely to arrive at good guesses by a more well-informed understanding of the empirical facts of human nature and the probable consequences of their various actions. Besides, to be of value, it doesn’t need to be perfect; it just needs to be better than what we have.

Colby wrote:

“Happiness” is probably not the ultimate good to which we are aspiring. Something like human “need” may be a stronger factor here. For example, if the moral issue we are dealing with is abortion, the amount of pleasure certain people may acquire in the long run from having performed the act says nothing about how this may affect humanity in general in the long run. For example, if abortion were legal at all times and under all circumstances, this may result in a large reduction in the human population overtime if it becomes the norm. This may also contribute to an overall disinterest in human preservation, resulting in apathy as it relates to other plights of humanity such as world hunger, war, etc. Those relate to our basic “needs” for survival both individually and collectively. Measuring something like happiness cannot possibly address these types of issues.

Ok, let me see if I understand your concern correctly: Unregulated abortion à rampant abortion à large reduction in human population à disinterest in human preservation and general apathy à world hunger, war, etc. Yikes, Colby, no wonder you’ve got such strong feelings about abortion! First of all, I have to say that I find your hypothetical scenario highly unlikely. Even so, if unregulated abortion did lead to all the horrors you mentioned, then my account would simply conclude that it was not the morally correct one – not because it resulted in the lack of our basic needs, but because it diminished our collective wellbeing. But remember that I defined happiness in terms of satisfying an individual’s fundamental interests, which besides wants, hopes, and desires, also included needs. (Probably a better term than “happiness” would be Aristotle’s “eudaimonia,” or flourishing. I just didn’t want to scare anyone off.) But needs is kind of a slippery concept in relation to human happiness and morality, because we tend to associate the term so strongly with survival, and morality ranks many values higher than strict survival (for some good examples of this, see Harry Frankfurt’s essay “The Importance of What We Care About”).

Colby wrote:

Part of answering the question of whether or not science can address moral issues is not looking at the hypothetical of what science MIGHT be able to answer if it had all of the right technology, but what science CAN answer now.

At least as relevant to the debate as your question above is the question of what other alternatives we have. Insofar as we’re all still committed to not assuming the thing we’re aiming to prove, namely the divine authorship of the Christian Bible, we need to be careful not to hold science to the standard of an omniscient God. I’m not trying to argue that given the choice between science and God, we should prefer science as our ultimate moral authority. What I’m trying to argue is that given the choice between science and any religious text whose divine authorship is still open to doubt, we should perhaps consider science the best that we’ve got. Rather than the question posed above, then, we should really be asking two questions: first, How does science compare NOW in addressing moral matters compared to our traditional (religious) authorities? (to which I’d answer “pretty well, but needs some work”); and second, How much promise does science have for addressing moral matters in the FUTURE if we continue to develop it compared to our traditional authorities? (to which I’d answer, “very much, I think, and hardly worth comparing to the traditional authorities”).

Don’t get me wrong, I think Christian morality represents a huge advancement from many earlier ethical systems, and the New Testament, at least, is still a half-decent approximation to contemporary morality. But the fatal flaw with most religion-based moral systems, in my assessment, and the reason they’ll never be able to compete with science in moral potential, is their claim to finality or ultimacy. A book containing claims to (capital-T) Truth and (capital-K) Knowledge in an empirical world is tantamount to having an expiration date printed on its cover. Imagine if science were governed by that same tendency, and after the chapter on Newtonian physics, we just decided to write “The End” (“and a curse be on anyone who adds or takes away from the words of this book”). Morality is a science, as far as I’m concerned: the science of human wellbeing. And like any science, when it stops growing and changing, it dies in both relevance and credibility. As I’ve tried to argue before, we don’t need facts to ground morality, and we don’t need knowledge to ground authority. On the contrary, in an empirical world in which facts are always provisional and open to future revision, a presumption of knowledge can only undermine someone’s credibility and moral authority. The modesty and conservatism of science are the reason both for its present inadequacies in addressing moral issues as well as for its unique promise for being able to address these issues in the future. The domain of morality needs a scientific ethos, in my opinion, and what better than science itself to provide it?

Colby wrote:

Something like the Bible or even philosophy can look at [moral] issues from a subjective standpoint because that is what they claim to do, but if science only has facts, I still cannot see how it addresses these issues. Describing empirical facts does not tell us what to do with those empirical facts.

First of all, the interpretation of Christianity that I’m most familiar also teaches that morality is objective, i.e., that it is grounded either in God’s command or his nature. Many theists even think that the objectivity of morality entails God’s existence, and therefore serves as one of the proofs of his existence (this is the so-called moral argument for God). So why is the objectivity of morality non-problematic when it’s found in Christianity, but problematic when it’s found in naturalism? Could you clarify how it is that the “subjective standpoint” is supposed to figure into Christianity’s supposed ability to address moral issues?

Regardless, the reason I believe that science can address moral issues is because some of the facts it deals with are facts about human beings. In other words, subjects, themselves, represent huge reservoirs of objective facts. What Colby likes and doesn’t like, what makes Colby happy and unhappy, what are Colby’s hopes and fears, are all objective facts, i.e., facts whose existence and particular properties don’t depend on Colby’s thoughts about them (proved by the fact that Colby can have false beliefs about these things). Probably the majority of these facts are fixed to a large extent by Colby’s genetics. Many of those that remain unfixed by genetics probably become fixed soon after, either during fetal development or in the first years of Colby’s childhood. The point is that, if some of Colby’s preferences exist as they do independently of Colby’s thoughts about them, then they are by definition – or certain definitions, I should say – objective.

Of course, being objective doesn’t in itself make something the appropriate subject of scientific inquiry: it must also be empirical, i.e., perceptible through the five senses. God’s existence is supposed to be an objective fact, but not an empirical one, since God qua spirit is not perceptible through the five senses.[10] God therefore falls outside the domain of science. Likewise, 2+2=4 is considered objectively true, but its truth is analytical, not empirical. So my view holds that some of people’s preferences are not only objective, but also empirical. I’m less confident in this claim than I am the first one, but naturalistic reductionist views hold that mental states are reducible to (physical) brain states, which provides a plausible explanation of how the innate preferences and interests of human beings might serve as suitable subjects of scientific inquiry.

The last detail of my view is just that morality is grounded in these objective, empirical facts about human beings, i.e., that moral imperatives derive from the innate preferences and interests of individual human beings.

So, in summary, the reason that science can address moral issues is, on my view, because:

(1)  If x is both objective and empirical, then x falls within the domain of science and science can address x.
(2)  The innate preferences and interests of human beings are objective
(3)  The innate preferences and interests of human beings are empirical
(4)  Morality is grounded in the innate preference and interests of individual human beings
(5)  Therefore, science can address morality

Anyway, I don’t want to give the impression that your objection isn’t a serious one – it is, and a lot of people share it. Nonetheless, I’m confident that it can be overcome, and I’ve made at least a few attempts to show how. If the one above doesn’t work for you, maybe you can try reading one of my more extended attempts here: http://muckrunner.blogspot.com/2013/10/ethical-statements-are-ordinary.html. I also make an argument similar to this one in my paper “A Volitional Account of Moral Obligations,” which you can find here: http://muckrunner.blogspot.com/2011/07/volitional-analysis-of-moral.html.

Colby wrote:

Can you perhaps provide a different example or put things more in perspective using the example I gave (abortion) and explain how science can answer this from a moral perspective based on what we can do NOW? Actually, if possible, please expound on the abortion example. I think that is a good example because it is a polarizing issue and has major moral implications.

Sure, I can give it a shot. Unfortunately, it’s going to have to wait, because it’s going to require a lot of work. Besides, I think I’ve already worn everyone out with this response, so I don’t want to press my luck any farther.


[2] It’s often said that our desires do not seek to represent the world as it is, as our beliefs aim to do, but rather as we would like for it be. See, e.g., Michael Smith, The Moral Problem, (Malden: Blackwell Publishing, 1994), 115.
[3] See Matthew C. Bagger’s article “The Ethics of Belief: Descartes and the Augustinian Tradition” in The Journal of Religion, Vol. 82, No. 2 (Apr., 2002), pp. 205-24 for a good discussion on this subject.
[4] The Will to Believe, 36.
[5] I agree with Kierkegaard that imagination and will are much more important. See Training in Christianity, 168-172; Fear and Trembling, 16-17.
[6] The Will to Believe, 36.
[10] John 4:24, Col. 1:15, etc.

29 comments:

  1. Here are finally my responses to some of the comments. I believe a majority, if not all, are Colby's comments from the Preface discussion.

    These responses were written fairly quickly and mostly off the top of my head, so I apologize if any arguments I make are riddled with fallacy or aren't as clear and concise as they could be. At any rate, know that I'm not as serious as I may sound in the tone of my responses. Since no one in this discussion has met me, I can see how I might come off as a little pretentious, which is the last thing I want.

    Hopefully I've added to the discussion and not introduced too many new rabbit trails or holes. And most importantly, I hope I've competently presented some kind of challenge to some of the claims made here.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Response 1:

    1. This may be cliché, but the concept of the big bang and even the theory of evolution are both examples. Both are called 'theory' in part because there is simply not enough information available to us at the moment to empirically demonstrate the factual nature of both concepts. However, both the big bang and evolution are taught as if there is zero doubt that both are true. We are all told "this is the way it happened," not "this is how we think it probably happened."

    Well, I think one difficulty with your objection that "there is simply not enough information to us to empirically demonstrate the factual nature of both concepts" is too broad a statement, or at least omitting a lot of existing evidence or redefining what a "fact" really is. In other words, it smacks of an argument from incredulity, which one would expect to be frequent in discussions like these. How much is not enough information? At what level do we need to delve to before a "fact" is established? These aren't hypotheses that we're talking about here. Perhaps it would help if you presented what you think is an example of a fact to narrow it down. But for now, I'll go into why I think we have quite a bit of information at the moment to empirically demonstrate the factual nature of at least evolution (the big bang is not quite the cosmogonical theory it once was, but it's the best one so far, so I'll give you that) and how geology, a field you omitted from your comment, has especially caused problems for the empirical claims of the Bible.

    First, since you brought up evolution as an example, predictions made within evolution like endemic species, transitional fossils, genetics, and the geological record have all come to fruition and all complement each other, and some of these happened post-Darwin, that is, he predicted these would be the case if evolution were true, and that's not just coincidental (although there are groups who believe it's all a conspiracy, including the Flat Earth Society, Gene Ray's "Timecube," and others). So, my point is that there are heaps of evidence that provide us with plenty of information to empirically demonstrate that evolution is definitely true at a high level (e.g., look at the extreme variations in dog breeds and how selecting for certain traits fits with evolution and gives breeders real results), and more plausibly true at the granular level (e.g., it is more challenging to demonstrate before you the evolutionary "steps" of the cell wall). If it was a bad theory or if there wasn't a single grain of truth to be found within it, scientists would have thrown it out a long time ago with many others. I believe String Theory will be going this way in the next several years. Also, this theory is only hundreds of years old and took some time to become accepted--the time it took to validate these predictions, as well as more modern findings, eventually demonstrated that evolution is highly plausible in many areas and indeed fact at higher levels--it is such a broad theory that were you to even swat a fly, it would still fit in with evolution and you would be contributing to it. Is it "fact" by your definition? Not entirely it would seem, but by your definition, neither is gravity.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Second, all of this empirical evidence does not only apply to evolution, but to geology as well (and as I said, they complement each other). Both cause great problems for the empirical claims of the Bible, especially the geological discovery of an old earth and the debunking of a global flood, two points I'm sure you're familiar with. I have yet to see any convincing reconciliation of an old earth with the biblical claim that it was created in six, literal days, especially when in the Hebrew text it states that the universe was created in literal, 24-hour days based on the Hebrew word "yom" as well as the consistency of "yom" throughout the Bible that validates this--it takes a lot of wriggling to get out of it. (1) When we contrast the creationist account with the empirical evidence geology has provided us with today, we see that things don't add up, i.e., the two views conflict.

    ReplyDelete
  4. For instance, in this article, the author Christopher Gregory Weber compiled a number of sources (which he lists at the bottom of his article) to make some of these comparisons. He begins with the creationist account of the flood as presented by Dr. Henry Morris of The Institute for Creation Research (ICR) (and you can already see how much additional information must be added in order to geologically explain the global flood):

    The ICR [Institute for Creation Research] flood geology theory relates the events of the Biblical Flood as follows: Before the Flood, a water vapor "canopy" in the upper atmosphere created a greenhouse effect, making the entire earth a tropical paradise. The oceans were shallower, the lands lower and more extensive than today. Because the greenhouse effect kept temperatures the same throughout the earth, there was no wind circulation and no rain, only a mist that watered the ground daily. Underneath the earth lay vast underground water reservoirs.

    To start the Flood, God performed some miracles: He made the animals seek out Noah's Ark, "opened the windows of the heavens" to empty the vapor canopy on to the earth, and "broke the fountains of the great deep" to overwhelm the continents with volcanically heated brines. During the course of the flood, the violence of the rains and volcanic waters catastrophically scoured and dumped sediments, burying all sorts of creatures as fossils in the process. In and of itself, this catastrophic erosion and sedimentation was perfectly naturalistic; it operated according to ordinary laws of physics and chemistry, only on a much larger and faster scale than erosion and sedimentation today.

    One year later, to end the Flood, God performed one more set of miracles; he made the continents rise and the ocean basins sink along vertical faults. These new basins were necessary to contain all the ocean waters once they had been augmented with all the newly released canopy and subterranean waters. Thus ended the Flood of Noah; thus originated the face of the earth we see today.

    Modern creationists no longer calculate precise Biblical chronologies because they say there may be small gaps in some of them. Even so, they believe that God created the earth no earlier than ten thousand years ago, and brought on the Flood one or two thousand years after the Creation.

    This account summarizes the flood geology model that Dr. Henry M. Morris, Director of ICR, expounds and defends in creationist classics like The Genesis Flood (Whitcomb and Morris, 1961) and Scientific Creationism (1974).
    (2)

    ReplyDelete
  5. You might not entirely agree with Dr. Morris' assessment, but if you take the Bible literally (and you have to, otherwise it descends into slippery exegesis and the truth of the scripture becomes subjective and open to other interpretation, and even Dr. Morris takes liberty with it), you are obligated to accept this view of a global flood and the falsifiable geological implications this theory has.

    This is contrasted with actual geological findings, that is, the empirical evidence that proves a global flood is highly improbable. Does this mean evidence of a global flood could be found and really change what we know about geology? I suppose, but it would require a lot of work and a big find to topple the evidence we currently have against it. For instance (taken from the same source):

    The Grand Canyon contains fossil desert dunes and other sediments that to all appearances were deposited on dry land. The Permian Coconino Sandstones in the upper walls of the Grand Canyon have the frosted well-sorted well rounded sand grains found only in land-deposited sand dunes (Shelton, 1966). Furthermore, many of the laminae of the cross-bedding contain fossil footprints that could only have come from reptiles or other quadrupeds climbing up the face of a slightly damp sand dune in the open air. (Those climbing down the slopes left no tracks because they simply slid.) ICR geologist Dr. Steve Austin has taught the theory that amphibians resting between underwater dunes made the tracks. His theory is very interesting, but rather implausible since the Flood must have been violently dumping several meters' worth of sediment per day.

    The Canyon's Supai and Hermit Shales, found today beneath the Coconino Sandstones, look exactly like river deltas that formed above sea level (Shelton, 1966). Back in Permian times, many quadrupeds (probably reptiles) left their footprints in the soft delta mud. As the mud baked hard in the sun, it formed cracks. The hardness of the baked mud preserved the footprints and mudcracks until the flooded rivers of the rainy season buried them in fresh mud. These fossil prints and mudcracks are found today, as well as iron oxides that form in the open air, showing that these shales formed above sea level.

    . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    ReplyDelete
  6. In an article in some obscure religious journal cited in Robert Kofahl's Handy Dandy Evolution Refuter, flood geologist Harry Coffin maintains that the tree rings within a given fossil forest layer do not cross correlate. Let's look into this.

    Every year, a tree grows a new ring. If the rainfall varies from year to year where this tree grows, then all the rings in its wood will vary in diameter; the narrow rings grew during the dry years, and the wide ones during wet years. Dendrochronologists (tree-ring daters) correlate tree rings from different trees by comparing ring variation patterns in one tree with those in another to see whether they match.

    Since Coffin says the petrified trees of Specimen Ridge have rings that vary enough in diameter to be worth trying to correlate, he implies that before the Flood, rainfall varied from year to year. In this, he contradicts the flood geology model without knowing it (if he assumes with Morris that no rain fell in pre Flood times). Also, since the trees all supposedly died within the same year in the Flood, the flood geology theory implies that if their rings vary in diameter at all, then all the trees everywhere in the formation should cross-correlate. Thus Coffin's claims do not stand up under analysis.

    . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    The flood geology theory allows no more than about 8,000 years for all modern reefs to form, only 5% of the time that Eniwetok needed to grow to its present state. If flood geology is true, then the modern reefs started growing only after Noah's Flood was over with. After all, the Flood itself would have killed off all corals by kicking up a slurry of clay particles in all the ocean waters. These particles would have taken years to settle out. Corals require clear water and cannot stand any turbidity. Even though modern creationists allow gaps in the Biblical genealogies, standard ICR works like Scientific Creationism (General Edition) allow no more than several thousand years between Noah's Flood and today. To fit Eniwetok into their time constraints, the ICR creationists are forced to ignore the findings of Ladd.

    . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    According to the flood geology theory, all "kinds" of plants and animals alive today (not to mention dinosaurs and mammoths and other animals now extinct) lived on the earth before the flood. The Bible says Noah was to take specimens of every type of living air-breathing land animal aboard the Ark (Gen. 6:19-21; 7:2, 3, 8, 9, 15). Thus flood geology predicts that the fossil record should consist mostly of animal and plant species alive today. The extinct fossil species should be mostly delicate types sensitive to environment, because the Flood and the rugged conditions inside the Ark would have killed such creatures off. These predictions fit poorly with the available evidence.

    ReplyDelete
  7. So in these ways, and this is only one, cobbled together source, we can view both creation and the flood as two theories of how the earth appears to us in a certain way, but one has not stood the test of time and is quickly being replaced by better theories backed with greater evidence. I know time is not an indicator of the truth, and I want to make that distinction--I mean that science continues to build its foundation as new evidence is available while the other simply cannot. So in the same way as science, when we remove the "biblical" and "secular" labels, we see that they operate under the same methods and yield the same proper results as gauges for what is probably/accurately true and what is less likely to be true--basically, the better theory wins out, and the Bible's theories have not stood up to the evidence.

    I think I might have simplified your objection too much, but hopefully these examples demonstrate how we have plenty of empirical evidence to bolster these claims, and even if you leave evolution and the big bang out of it, you still have geology to deal with and all of its evidence, which again complements evolutionary theory. My goal was to demonstrate how there is plenty of empirical evidence for evolution especially, and how theory in the same way as molecular theory or the theory of gravity are still theories even though it would be very difficult to deny that they are facts.

    As far as teaching that these concepts are without a doubt taught as true, from my experience this has always been presented with the caveat as what the definition of "fact" is within theory and how theory is separate from hypothesis, the caveat that I have essentially demonstrated to you above. If you have citations or examples of what you mean, that would be helpful. Because with all the empirical evidence we currently have, how else would you suggest it be taught and how far do you go to establish it as truth about reality?

    ReplyDelete
  8. Response 2:

    3. Science books contain innumerable references to astronomical phenomena such as space, stars, planets, black holes, etc. Our understanding of these phenomena are based on limited observational methods (i.e., telescopes) and mathematical calculations. However, many of facts we have about these areas also lack empirical evidence since we simply cannot study them in a better way. As such, as technology advances, new “facts” come to light. For example, Pluto has been considered to have met whatever criteria were established to be called a planet, but now new information has come to light leading scientists to declassify it as a planet. Again, the trend here is that it’s former classification has always been “fact,” but now there is a new “fact”—Pluto is not a planet.

    You state further:

    "These are imperfect examples—no doubt. But my point here, and the point that I think Plantinga is aware of, is that science is not infallible. Each “fact” in time is often treated (or at least presented) as it is pure truth, but is then later proven to be false and a new “fact” arises, which will surely be replaced by something new later on. Science is unable to be that infallible source of truth many wish it were."

    For starts, I have to reference a short essay by Isaac Asimov, namely the portion of the text below because it is relevant to the crux of most of your points in this discussion to a great extent (I recommend reading the whole article):

    This particular thesis was addressed to me a quarter of a century ago by John Campbell, who specialized in irritating me. He also told me that all theories are proven wrong in time.

    My answer to him was, "John, when people thought the Earth was flat, they were wrong. When people thought the Earth was spherical, they were wrong. But if you think that thinking the Earth is spherical is just as wrong as thinking the Earth is flat, then your view is wronger than both of them put together.
    (3)

    Asimov's point is that even if new "facts" replace "old facts," even though a flat earth was never a fact to begin with, we are simply getting closer to the most specific definition of a thing. You can say "a raven is a bird," but if you say "a raven is of the genus corvus" you get even more specific. The earth isn't simply "round," but that is closer to the shape than a flat plane, so that's not simply incorrect either. I'll go into this more later.

    ReplyDelete
  9. So how do we define the primary objective of science? Physicist Sean Carroll puts it like this:

    I want to start with what I think is a non-controversial statement about what science is. Namely, science deals with empirical reality — with what happens in the world, i.e. what "is." Two scientific theories may disagree in some way — "the observable universe began in a hot, dense state about 14 billion years ago" vs. "the universe has always existed at more or less the present temperature and density." Whenever that happens, we can always imagine some sort of experiment or observation that would let us decide which one is right. The observation might be difficult or even impossible to carry out, but we can always imagine what it would entail. (Statements about the contents of the Great Library of Alexandria are perfectly empirical, even if we can't actually go back in time to look at them.) If you have a dispute that cannot, in principle, be decided with observable facts about the world, your dispute is not one of science. (4)

    Simply put, science is all about getting closer to the truth using empirical evidence and testing this evidence through experimentation to yield verifiable results. To throw this evidence away or get to the point where you're questioning "what is really fact?" or saying "well that's subjective/your opinion" is really just making excuses when you have no doubt that the earth is an oblate spheroid, or more specifically a geoid when factoring in gravitational pull, or that if you slam your finger in a door it will probably hurt (note: I know you take issue with the former example--with the former, you can say that you have never seen the earth from space, but with the latter that you have experienced that painful incident, so the two are not the same--I go into this in greater detail in a later response). In either case, to begin to question "how do you know it exists?" is to retreat into solipsism and equally works against your argument by placing the burden of proof on you for the existence of a creator since you cannot use the same empirical argument to support your own biblical evidence that is also based on empirical evidence (at least the historically valid portions). This conditional faith is what you have to help cement your belief in the Bible, which I go into in greater detail as well in a later response.

    ReplyDelete
  10. As for your Pluto statement, at this point, the relatively newly discovered "planet" Pluto has been studied carefully and has been found to be a dwarf planet. So your claim is that you can't trust science when it gets closer to the truth or when it is in the process of getting closer to it? Pluto is more of a planet than, say, the moon--after all, it is considered "the least massive planet" in the solar system thus far, and has since been labelled a dwarf. So what's your point? You're simply saying that science starts at the top with little to no knowledge of a thing and then gets closer to the truth--to the bottom of things--by carefully inspecting the nature of that thing, which is exactly what science is all about. It's not like Pluto was discovered to be a nebula or something even further from the truth--we are just now closer to understanding what Pluto really is just as science has done with everything else. Some of these challenges are easier than others, of course. The Hadron Collider has helped us get closer to the truths about quantum mechanics, those very same mechanics and phenomena that exist all throughout the universe. Don't forget that the universe is composed of a limited amount of matter--as Carl Sagan said, "we are made of star stuff." So to say that we cannot apply these principles to the cosmos is not entirely true, even if currently some of this requires rigorous thought experiment and mathematical justification. As another commentator in this discussion said, To fault science, then, for “changing its mind” whenever new evidence comes to light is just misguided. Science is supposed to change its mind. That’s what lends it its credibility. So while we might justly criticize the tendency of scientists themselves to exaggerate the finality of their favorite scientific theories, this criticism doesn’t carry over to science itself.

    So again, theories are testable and the best ones still hold up to a lot of scrutiny. Einstein's predictions through general relativity are still holding up to scrutiny, even in the last few years, and as one example, has been tested recently when a star pair (a neutron star orbited by a white dwarf) allowed for both a massive and quantum experiment to test both general relativity and quantum theory to see which one could better explain the phenomena.

    In one article, it states that according to general relativity "This particular binary star system should radiate ripples in space-time, known as gravitational waves" (5), which is exactly what happened.

    Paulo Freire of the Max Planck Institute stated "Our radio observations were so precise that we have already been able to measure a change in the orbital period of 8 millionths of a second per year — exactly what Einstein's theory predicts." (Ibid)

    Even though physicists are currently working on reconciling general relativity with quantum physics and ultimately quantum gravity, the theory still holds up to scrutiny. Rather than saying "see, they don't complement each other," we have to be patient as physicists continue to work on answering these questions; not knowing the answers to these questions at the moment does not make it untrue either--it is merely the limitation of our knowledge at this point. We have now established that it is a fact (although you might disagree) that the earth is old, whales and homo sapiens are mammals, ontogeny does not recapitulate phylogeny, and that Pluto is a dwarf planet. To suppose that a new fact will "surely replace" the fact that the earth is not nor was it ever composed of four corners I would think is a greater challenge.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. *Note: I would also like to add another, more practical application of Einstein's relativity: the GPS.

      Dr. Michio Kaku briefly explains how this works:

      Since Einstein derived his famous equation, literally millions of experiments have confirmed his revolutionary ideas. For example, the GPS system, which can locate your position on the Earth to within a few feet, would fail unless one added in corrections due to relativity. (Since the military depends on the GPS system, even Pentagon generals have to be briefed by physicists concerning Einstein's theory of relativity.) The clocks on the GPS actually change as they speed above the earth, as Einstein predicted.

      Source: Physics of the Impossible: A Scientific Exploration into the World of Phasers, Force Fields, Teleportation, and Time Travel; p. 201; Kaku, Michio; Random House LLC, Mar 11, 2008

      Delete
  11. Response 3:

    And I should mention something very important about what I just mentioned above—more of a question, really—is this really at all different from the knowledge most of us have about anything, especially in science? Has anyone witnessed the “big bang?” Have you personally observed macro-evolution (or even micro-evolution) take place? Have you been in an environment in which gravity does not exist (i.e., space)? Have you seen the double-helix of a DNA strand? If the answer is “no” to those questions (and it IS “no” for each one for all of us in this discussion at least), on what are your beliefs based? Most likely it is through some limited empirical evidence (maybe doing some science experiment in high school or college), and is then mostly based on some outside source. Scientists tell us this is how it works. Science books tell us this. Do we know these scientists? If their work is approved through some board, do we know anything about the reliability of that group? Do we know if anyone else was there to double-check and verify their claims? How do we know our science books, their publishers, editors, and writers are reliable? They may tell us they are (or someone else tells us that that other group is reliable and that guy that wrote it is therefore reliable), but why should we trust them if we have not observed it ourselves? You could say you have seen science in action, but really, how much have you personally observed? What percentage of your knowledge of the universe would you say is based on non-personally empirical data? I would estimate something like less than 99% of it, and I suspect that is the case for all of us. As such, how is this different from a Christian’s belief in God or scripture? You can tell me there is a massive host of reasons that science is considered reliable by means of the reliability of its proponents (i.e., scientists, writers, etc.), and I can say with confidence that the same is true of the scriptures. People have devoted their entire lives to studying different aspects of science, but people have also devoted their entire lives to studying the scriptures in their original languages, studying other historic data from other cultures before, during, and after the Biblical events, doing archaeological digs, etc., verifying the claims of the scripture. How are these two fields different in their reliability?

    This is a good point, and a big one that I've probably misinterpreted in a number of ways in my following responses. At its core, I've identified it as an argument from ignorance because we would have to accept many radical claims, or at least think them plausible, if we really used only personal observances as our core tool for validating information. One classic demonstration of why this is (and sorry if this is really common knowledge) is Earl Bertrand Russell's teapot analogy.

    In any case, I'll break your points up and go into them a little further based on my understanding of what your objection is using some other kind of rhetoric to try to make a case against this. I've broken my responses up into four parts and have labelled these as "Response 3-a," "Response 3-b," and so on. Also, I should note that these next responses are completely based on my own reasoning and not based on any philosophical source, so someone better versed in philosophy (i.e., Patrick) will easily be able to keep my thoughts in check and explain to me any fallacies or misunderstanding of concepts that I've committed (although I have anticipated the holes in my logic).

    ReplyDelete
  12. Response 3-a:

    Has anyone witnessed the “big bang?” Have you personally observed macro-evolution (or even micro-evolution) take place? Have you been in an environment in which gravity does not exist (i.e., space)? Have you seen the double-helix of a DNA strand?

    Personally, like I stated in my very first response (remember that one, so long ago up the page?), theories like the big bang, while backed by rigorous mathematical justification, are not quite as up to par as evolution, general/special relativity, or geology, like I stated earlier--there are some theories that are at the point where it would be difficult to go further with them, and the big bang is not one of them. In any case, the answer is no, but I've never witnessed a live birth or a human being's death either, just as I have not witnessed Washington's crossing of the Delaware, the resurrection of Jesus, or personally witnessed Louis Slotin lose control of the screwdriver preventing the demon core from going critical in 1946. I sincerely I hope I'm not misunderstanding your objection, but from what I can tell, the real crux of your argument rests on "personal experience is the only source of truth," or at least, that personal experience makes something more or less truthful in some form and cannot be true if you cannot personally experience it. The important distinction that needs to be made here is that personal experience alone does not make something more or less of a truth, but rather that it is another way to validate the truth along with other methods. To say this is to denounce the existence of things whenever they are not experienced/perceived by you and also would require you to consider a variety of other ludicrous claims (like teapots in orbit), as classic thought experiments have attempted to tackle. But I will go into more detail in Response 3-b and 3-c (note: If I have completely misunderstood you here, then read on, laugh, and be entertained, if nothing else).

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. *Note: I should also mention that I experience "micro" and, without even knowing it or holding to retrocausality, "macro" evolution just by existing! The theory is so broad, that as I mentioned above, my every action as it relates to nature and natural selection (that ongoing agent in the background) that our every action contributes to evolution and to our existence that even swatting a fly affects the outcome of all living things in the grand scheme (I'll let you make the chaos theory correlation and call that "macro" evolution).

      Delete
  13. Response 3-b:

    Scientists tell us this is how it works. Science books tell us this. Do we know these scientists? If their work is approved through some board, do we know anything about the reliability of that group? Do we know if anyone else was there to double-check and verify their claims? How do we know our science books, their publishers, editors, and writers are reliable? They may tell us they are (or someone else tells us that that other group is reliable and that guy that wrote it is therefore reliable), but why should we trust them if we have not observed it ourselves?

    Like I prefaced in my last point, the truth of something is not necessitated exclusively by your personal experience of it. You personally experience dreams and nightmares, yet you don't believe them to be actual, true events. Also, by this logic, you could also say that you have never personally experienced The Statue of Liberty, yet there is a reason why you believe it exists, and that Staten Island and New York exist, and so forth--certainly this is easier to believe in and justify than little green men or teapots in orbit. I think what you are getting at is that at some point we have to accept something as the truth through faith when we finally arrive at the most granular level (and maybe that was obvious). But if you are saying that truth can only be derived from personal experience and that these personal experiences are the only source of truth (which is what I think you are saying), then we have to ask "why stop here?"

    In this latter case, if you reduce truth to only personal experience, then at what point do you accept the experience you are having as anything but illusory? As in, if you leave a room containing only one chair, does the chair and the room it is in disappear the moment you leave the room because you are no longer personally experiencing it? And if a video camera was in that room and showed you on a monitor outside the room that the chair and room were still there, would you believe it even though you aren't physically in the room? I will go into this in greater detail in the next paragraph and explain why the latter must lead to the former in the end, that is, why in the end it requires accepting truth through faith as a stopping point like in the former case, and then in Response 3-c, why the former is an incorrect presupposition for determining the truth in and of itself because in the end it is borderline solipsistic and indeterminate (note: This really sounds like I am setting up a straw man/slippery slope argument, and if this is what has happened, please clarify and I will go about it differently. I am basing these rebuttals on the premise that "personal experience is the only source of truth").

    ReplyDelete
  14. If truth can only be derived from personal experience, then at what point do we stop and accept the experience as true? We can keep going until we get to an quantum, irreducible point, or infinite regress, for instance and more relevant to your point, if we asked a certain experimental physicist to show us her or his credentials and then verified them against university records and so forth. But at what point to you accept that it's true, and even still, that the information she or he learned could be verified based on where the professors gained their knowledge from before in the first place, and then reducing it to her or his research and textbooks and where those were written and published and then meeting the publishers and so on and accepting any of these as true based on experiencing them? I think this is really where this objection is going, but if it is, then you can never really be certain of anything. Because, as you know, the scientific community is all about the peer review and it is a requirement to document the individuals who reviewed the work (at least two controversies regarding this off the top of my head were the Antony Flew case and Michael Behe's "Darwin's Black Box"), but this wouldn't be helpful in this instance; it would be superfluous because you might still get to the point of saying "but how do I know that's true, and how do I know that that's true?" and so on and so on even after meeting those reviewers in person. Obviously going through and investigating these cases through documentation or other sources wouldn't suffice--would personally experiencing the documents regarding the case be enough, or would meeting those on the review panel be sufficient? Why one over the other? How could you ever be sure that any of what you are experiencing, e.g., by hearing the cases from the individuals on the panel, is true? If it was convincing, why would you stop there and say "okay, I'm convinced?" How much evidence from how many sources would be convincing, and why that amount and for what reasons? You would never be able to personally experience all of these sources at the most granular level, and in an extreme instance of this thinking, simultaneously.

    ReplyDelete
  15. In regards to how far you're willing to reduce it until you get to a point of accepting the validity of the information, you've already pulled the rug out from under it by stating that you cannot prove that any knowledge outside personal experience is true, or can be trusted, which really leads to "how can I prove my personal experiences are true at all?" or questions concerning reality like "how do I know when I put my cup in the cupboard that it will still be there when I open the door again?" What I mean is, cutting out the middle man of credentials and publishers and getting to the source of the information would still require you to accept that information as true at some point--based on this line of extreme skepticism, you would never get there; there can exist no truth but your own. But certainly getting to that point would not be without conviction or volition because your very practices would confirm your beliefs and what you believe to be true--to have to be coerced so greatly in accepting the truth of "a measure-zero-set is a null set" or "a raven is black" is a little ridiculous. If you readily accept these as truths, then you have not accepted them without real belief because your genuine conviction has overridden this condition, that is, you arrived at your belief at some point through a variety of means that are extremely convincing. For instance, in the "all ravens are black" example, you could ask anyone in the world in any language that has seen and understands what a raven is (assuming you are in parts of the world that contains ravens) and they would tell you "black" in their native tongue. Imagine forfeiting all your knowledge and becoming completely isolated because you could never bring yourself to accepting common, universal truths like these, or would have to pretend to accept them based on universal assumptions. And language and speech are an entirely different matter altogether. However, with these examples, getting to the point of accepting them as reality and a universal truth (e.g., that a raven is black; a raven is a bird; a raven is of the genus Corvus) is obviously very real, and it doesn't require "an act of faith" to believe unless you happen to be an anti-realist. But if I use say "scientists are beginning to call birds 'avian dinosaurs;' therefore all birds are avian dinosaurs," you would be more skeptical and would have to wait for more evidence or come to a point once more evidence accumulated that it was a truth as much as a raven is black and a bird and of the genus Corvus. Furthermore, you would never have an axiom from which to begin. Currently from what I can tell, you have a strong conviction that the Christian God of the Bible exists and is interested in human affairs, and this has not required any personally observable empirical data for you to come to this belief and is seemingly phenomenological.

    So hopefully I've kind of demonstrated why believing entirely this way is impractical, if not impossible, and how all knowledge would be illusory if you could never come to the point of truth except through surrender or being convinced that this was all some kind of sick trick. In the next point, I'll take it to the universal level and how this kind of extreme skepticism applies to other persons.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. *Note: I also have to mention that I just realized another commentator (Patrick maybe?) used "black crows" as an example. I assure you this is coincidental, and our uses of the examples differ slightly (like I used ravens . . .), but our points align to some degree. I think they somewhat align in my tiresome mention of having to accept that there could be a teapot in orbit, or as the commentator states, square circles because it is possible (but not plausible) that they could be discovered in the future. This isn't the only point the commentator makes, but I think it's one simple part where they align.

      One other thing neither of us goes into (unless I missed it in the commentator's post) is that our understanding or experience of colors, such as black if we assume it's a true color, are not adequate ways of truly verifying our perception of color. What I mean by this is that my black could be your red and we would never know--rods and cones as far as we know are too spread out to really make sense of it. However, even if this is the case (to say that my black is your red), our experiences are still attributed to that particular color, meaning that even if blood were "black" to you, it would still affect you "instinctually" or on your experiences as far as the association of pain or injury and so forth. However, what I'm trying to say (albeit poorly) is that within our construct of language that what we call "black" is still universally understood to mean that shade that could also simultaneously be different depending on the perceiver--this means that the objectivity of the color lies in our ability to identify it universally, yet "subjectively" (i.e., I cannot swap brains with you to know if my black is your red) based on the experience of that color. For this reason, we could agree "pastels are muted" or "red is an 'aggressive' color" (you know, within reason). I am saying this to better clarify my example of "all ravens are black" and that this fact would be agreed upon universally. Perhaps if someone said it isn't, the fact that their perception is skewed in regards to the construct of color that we have created in order to identify the colors of things would mean they are suffering from color blindness, which can be tested. This excludes synesthesia or even greater details like the Himba tribe, which I have read have a broad range for color, which means their perception is going to be less specific, so saying "what shade of black is this bird?" might be more challenging.

      Delete
  16. Response 3-c:

    You could say you have seen science in action, but really, how much have you personally observed? What percentage of your knowledge of the universe would you say is based on non-personally empirical data? I would estimate something like less than 99% of it, and I suspect that is the case for all of us.

    Again, this is certainly a good point as it pertains to your previous ones, but again, it's borderline solipsistic. How do you prove "something like less than 99% of it"? This extends epistemically into evaluating what true knowledge really is, which would take quite some time to lay out, and I don't think this is necessarily where you intended to go (also, I would not do it justice). But I will make an attempt to demonstrate how you might have arrived at this figure and why this level of skepticism, or extreme empiricism, to my mind, is a dangerous, lonely precipice, and impossible in practice.

    Building on the last point, I showed how personal experiences alone cannot validate the truths of reality and that a certain point, one must accept the truth as only within her or his personal experience or have no beliefs about reality at all. This only dealt with the consequences at a personal level; but if you extend this claim universally, you assume that each person has a limited amount of personally observed, empirical experiences (and again, this obligatorily extends to all knowledge both empirical because it is contained within you personally), and you combine all these experiences per person, the whole still amounts to nothing because you can never be everyone at once--each person has only her or his personal experiences, so gaining knowledge from any of them is fruitless because it can't be experienced from their perspective. So what you are in effect saying is that unless you can know everything through personal experience, and yours alone, you can only at any given time know what you personally experience, hence everybody cumulatively knowing nothing (because person A would have to know everything person B knows, which is impossible). Furthermore based on this line of thinking, if you can only rely on personal, empirical experiences, it is obligatory that the past is illusory; this is to say, it is merely an impression that can never be validated, and your state of knowledge would constantly be reset to zero at a "tabula rasa" state (e.g., memories of experiences you had cannot be validated any longer by personal, empirical experience because memories are not immediately empirical); you can only trust what you are experiencing at the present moment, so to say "if I touch a hot stove, I will get burned" relies on past experiences that you cannot validate until you experience it presently over and over because your knowledge relies completely on what you are experiencing at only the current moment. And even if you include past experiences as retained empirical data, these are still yours alone and the assumption that they are universally experienced this way without proof (e.g., mathematics, scientific proofs) or a concrete foundation for defining reality outside your own personal perceptions would be impossible. Imagine if this really were the case, if this were really what you believed? Basically, if truth about reality is based on your experience alone, then you could never be sure about anything. You could see the double-helix of a DNA strand and still not accept it unless you say that it exists within your own reality, which you would then also have to accept as my reality if I told you that I saw a conchospiral instead of a double-helix, which might garner funny looks from everyone else in the room. In other words, reality can't exist with this kind of thinking.

    ReplyDelete
  17. With this line of thought, I can see where you would arrive at a figure like "99%" and in fact could also tack on a ".9%" to that because that remaining 0.1% would only serve as the present moment you are experiencing. You would have to really limit yourself, and I think it would be impossible to put this kind of thinking into practice and not be ruled by what you do know, although there certainly existed extreme skeptics like Gorgias who tried. This line of thinking would allow for continuing to believe in a flat earth because you could never see it from space, that the sun is a giant light bulb because you could never prove it was a star, and other radical claims about reality (that some like Gene Ray really do hold to).

    So how do we come to the truth if it's not simply through personal, empirical experiences alone? How do we determine what reality really is and accept that the reviewers listed at the bottom of a page in a scientific journal really are who they say they are, even after validating the information through a variety of sources? Where do we draw the line without going down the slippery slope that this kind of thinking obligates us to do when we delve to an infinite regress? Obviously "the test of time" isn't necessarily a good way, nor popular opinion. A person's credentials can be verified, but as you've stated, assuming they are an authority is not always the best idea. Physics and science in general deal with reality and investigate many phenomena that fool our senses into thinking a thing is one way when it is in fact another--the tools used to prove why these phenomena exist and why they behave the way they do are the ways we arrive at the truth about a thing as it deals with reality, that is, the way things really are. Buckminster Fuller felt that instead of saying "upstairs" and "downstairs" we should be saying "outstairs" and "instairs" and "worldaround" instead of "worldwide" because that is a more true way of putting it as it deals with reality, in these instances the gravitational center of the earth and the shape of the earth. Just because we do not use these terms because they never became popular does not mean that these are not more correct ways of describing reality in our everyday lives. But this answer still won't suffice because we would have to come to an agreement on what reality is and belief and much more. However, I hope I at least demonstrated how personal experience is too subjective, requires all truth to be as such, and also requires accepting or considering other more radical claims that could exist within reality, like teapots in orbit.

    And lastly, this is basically a classic rationalist vs. empiricist question that Patrick would be better suited (i.e., more qualified) to address--that is, if you trust his credentials! We could also go into "if a tree falls in a forest and there is no one to hear it, does it still make a sound?" and assorted brain in vat scenarios that can be entertaining, but ultimately tedious at best. In the end, this is ultimately an "absence of evidence does not mean evidence of absence" argument.

    ReplyDelete
  18. Response 3-d:

    As such, how is this different from a Christian’s belief in God or scripture? You can tell me there is a massive host of reasons that science is considered reliable by means of the reliability of its proponents (i.e., scientists, writers, etc.), and I can say with confidence that the same is true of the scriptures. People have devoted their entire lives to studying different aspects of science, but people have also devoted their entire lives to studying the scriptures in their original languages, studying other historic data from other cultures before, during, and after the Biblical events, doing archaeological digs, etc., verifying the claims of the scripture. How are these two fields different in their reliability?

    Simply put, science deals with empirical evidence and tests the evidence and the Bible contains untestable claims like miracles and seraphims, extraordinary claims that inconveniently do not happen today (and of course there are Christian explanations for why this is). Other than some historical validity, there are just far too many claims the Bible makes that we could never validate as truth, and those that we have validated like in my previous examples have shown whether these claims are true or false based on real, tangible evidence. Furthermore, we have scholars and historians well-versed in epic poems like Beowulf. This certainly does not make the account of Beowulf true.

    As for "archaeological digs" and so forth, this is validating history--those valid, historical claims of the Bible make sense when you consider that the oral tradition and writings were just regurgitating real history during the time of the events (and even this is general as many numbers are rounded and specific dates and ages are scarce, which makes sense based on how it was passed down). Why wouldn't the technology and history from those times reflect what actually happened in accordance to what history outside of the Bible tells us? Other than these historical claims, which can be verified empirically (and some like the existence of Babel, chariots and skeletons of Egyptian soldiers at the bottom the Red Sea, and others minus several hoaxes are still in the works), the rest is a stretch. One would hope that it would at the very least fall in line with "secular" historical evidence, but it also falters in many of these areas as well. There is even difficulty in finding eyewitness accounts of Jesus' crucifixion outside of the Bible, which must utilize limited accounts through persons of that day such as Josephus, not to mention verses that contradict the practices of Roman civilization, and numerous others. In these ways, the Bible is not a reliable tool for history, let alone science.

    ReplyDelete
  19. Response 4:

    "Many people believe that “faith” simply means belief without evidence. But if I say I have faith in my wife, that she will stay committed to me, this isn’t simply belief without evidence. I may not be able to say with 100% certain or based on empirical evidence (i.e., seeing the future) that this is true, but there is a host of factors that contribute to the legitimacy of my faith in her. The same is true as it relates to the Bible. There are many factors that contribute to my belief that the Bible is true and is in fact authoritative in many aspects of life. As such, my confidence in this should extend as far as the evidence allows."

    I would agree that your confidence should extend as far as the evidence allows, including within your example. However, your example, which is one I've heard before (John Lennox used this example in a debate), is far easier to evaluate than any of the fantastical claims of the Bible, i.e., this example is not a good comparison for faith in God--it is a weak analogy. These are two different kinds of faith, one that is conditional and the other that is unconditional. This is based on the definition that gives faith the meaning "confidence or trust in a thing" and more extremely, "belief that does not rely on logical proof or material evidence." The Bible is a combination of both, but the belief that Jesus was the Son of God, that Samson, equipped only with the jawbone of a donkey to make it more credible than it already was, slaughtered an entire army by his lonesome, and other assorted miracles are of the unconditional sort. Belief that Luke was a great historian and that Pontius Pilatus was a real person are of the conditional sort. You have seen the evidence for and against many of the conditional faith-based Biblical claims (because as of yet, there is no way to validate the unconditional claims), yet you have either chosen to ignore, find fault with, or try to adjust the evidence that is against these Biblical claims to fit with Biblical claims, which obviously requires a lot of twisting of scripture. This doesn't mean that Samson could not have or did not slaughter an entire army with only the jawbone of a donkey--I'm simply saying that at the present moment, we have no material evidence or any kind of proof for this event happening anywhere else than in the Bible and that it requires unconditional faith to accept as much as it would a teapot in orbit.

    ReplyDelete
  20. For instance, you currently conditionally trust your wife based on all the empirical evidence you have right now, and were that to change for the worse, you would get to the bottom of it to ensure your suspicions were correct, which is entirely a conditional kind of faith. This isn't extreme/unconditional faith that cannot be logically or empirically demonstrated, e.g., "my wife tells me she knows Santa Claus personally" and you would believe it based on your unconditional faith in her. The fact that your trust in her is based on the overwhelming evidence you currently have of her faithfulness to you means that you are not being unconditionally faithful to her yourself nor can you be because at any time you can evaluate your level of trust in her and your reasons why, making it impossible for you to truly have unconditional faith in her as long as that option is available (i.e., that option obligates a condition). The odds right now are in your favor based on all your experiences of her. So it's not unconditional faith, or hardly faith at all, but rather she has not yet broken your confidence or trust, which is more in line with the conditional faith definition. This is why if she were to tell you she knew Santa Claus personally, you would think she was joking or perhaps that she was schizophrenic all this time, and you would probably become concerned (and I have real life examples of this happening). Currently, I could simply ask why you have faith in her being loyal to you, and no doubt your answer wouldn't simply be "I just do." If she was a bad liar or had a history of being promiscuous, you probably wouldn't have married her in the first place. You would more likely say "because she has yet to show me that she is cheating and I have yet to find her cheating." However, if I ask you "why do you believe Balaam's donkey really spoke?" or "why do you believe Jesus was the Son of God and rose from the dead?" or "why do you believe the Bible, orally communicated and written by many men, and men alone, over thousands of years, is God-inspired and infallible?" you would have to tell me "I just do". See the difference? This is not unlike the infamous saying "God said it, I believe it, and that settles it". Now that is true, unconditional faith and the sort you are really talking about in regards to God--one is faith based on evidence and real, testable trust (e.g., your wife), and the other is unconditional faith based on no evidence and blind trust (e.g., miracles), so you can't compare the two. This unconditional faith can exist for a creator because the creator can never be tested (the Bible even explicitly says not to test God) and because God is believed to be benevolent and always in the right; he can do no wrong as long as you have faith that he cannot. If you have faith that he can do no wrong, what is there other than your own volition to stop having faith in him or his words? What can persuade you that these claims can't be tested in any way and that it is completely based on intuition or willing ignorance? It is certainly more than just evidence, and if it was really largely dependent on evidence, we wouldn't be having much of a debate.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. *Note: I know one could argue that books such as "Ruth" were written by a female author; however, the author is unknown and was most likely Samuel, the prophet.

      Delete
  21. As far as biblical claims are concerned, you have the historical validity of some of the text as I mentioned before, but largely the authoritative word has been replaced by geology and other aspects of science as I demonstrated in the last point--you have to resort to exegesis to make the Bible work with modern scientific evidence, like the creation of gap theory, and so forth. Sure this is similar to scientific theories in creating others to make current theories work (e.g., String Theory again), but science is malleable and the Bible is not, which means that science doesn't simply close the book on one theory and say "that solves that!" This extends from everything to science to ethical and moral questions (because the Bible closes the book on moral issues such as misogyny and civil rights). As another commentator stated (to save me from rambling some more, although it hardly matters at this point):

    But the fatal flaw with most religion-based moral systems, in my assessment, and the reason they’ll never be able to compete with science in moral potential, is their claim to finality or ultimacy. A book containing claims to (capital-T) Truth and (capital-K) Knowledge in an empirical world is tantamount to having an expiration date printed on its cover. Imagine if science were governed by that same tendency, and after the chapter on Newtonian physics, we just decided to write “The End” (“and a curse be on anyone who adds or takes away from the words of this book”).

    And that's exactly it--science can adjust as the truth is tested and verified; it keeps going. When the earth was a sphere, it wasn't just a sphere, it was tested indefatigably through a variety of methods of measurement until the finality revealed itself to be the shape we know today; it would be very difficult to go further. But what if we threw this out and stuck with "four corners of the earth" and ridiculed anyone who told us otherwise, which actually was a real historical dilemma in Galileo's time for believing "pagan" authors were correct, which went against biblical teaching (see the Galileo Affair)? Imagine if we continued to use cubits as our primary form of measurement because we were so strongly tied to the Bible. At what point did we say "it's all right to come up with The Calculus" or "sing other songs other than just The Psalms" (which some churches still insist upon doing)?

    The Bible as a scientific tool just doesn't work, and it's absurd to teach it as a science. It is great literature with historical backing like other great "secular" works, but this certainly does not make it infallible or true, and empirical tests and research have validated that which is and which isn't. Again, one requires real evidence, which allows for conditional faith and the other is based entirely on obstinate willingness and one's own volition and hence unconditional faith. If the Bible left out scientific claims and served exclusively as a didactic tool, some leeway could be given, but this is just not the case.

    As another commentator more concisely put it:

    So let me just ask: What evidence do we have to suggest that the Bible is infallible, or a faithful guide to truth or right behavior? It wouldn’t seem to be its ability to anticipate future scientific discoveries: e.g., the Bible seems to suggest that the earth is young, that languages originated at Babel, that mental illness is caused by demonic possession, etc. It wouldn’t appear to be the timelessness of its moral prescriptions, either: e.g., the God of the Bible prescribes genocide and seems to condone the treatment of women as property.

    ReplyDelete
  22. Response 5:

    "What does science tell us about the act of abortion?"

    What does the Bible tell us about abortion? Or stem cell research? Or GMOs? Or Feynman Diagrams? Do our pets go to heaven? If so, why not all the other animals who weren't fortunate enough to be pets? This builds on the end of the last response--the Bible tells us many things about what our morals and values should be that just don't hold up today or exist for the sake of existing.

    For instance, there is no justification for discrimination against gays, yet the Bible naturally tells us that we should discriminate against gays, and sadly it is still a big topic of debate in the new millennium, no doubt still attributed to these biblical origins. The Bible also tells us that those that do not have faith in Jesus Christ will go to hell (if you are a Christian, not according to Judaism, of course). Does this include aborted babies? The Bible does not say. The Bible also does not discriminate against pedophilia as there is no verse that explicitly tells us this is a moral wrong, and in fact, one could argue it encourages it, as a commentator stated ("the God of the Bible prescribes genocide and seems to condone the treatment of women as property"), as there are many verses that depict the negative treatment of young women, e.g., a young virgin to keep King David warm on his deathbed. Can you imagine such a thing taking place today? Whether King David copulated with her or not, it doesn't even matter--to even attempt to justify this act is ludicrous, but many do in order to justify their faith even though they are uncomfortable with certain points of the authoritative word of God (I have proof of this kind of justification in a following paragraph).

    Furthermore, Jesus clearly subscribed to these Old Testament beliefs including discriminating against homosexuality when you understand that he is the God of the Old and New Testaments in the flesh and is the same voice behind Paul and every other writer of his own word, the Bible. Some Christians seem to think that Jesus is exempt from these commands that they are reticent to accept, yet if he truly is God, he is logically obligated to support these views as God--there is no way around it except through exegesis, which is slippery at best.

    ReplyDelete
  23. And of course, you run into a trap if you believe aborted babies go to heaven, because the babies are slated for heaven in either case. If you argue that it is still morally wrong because you are "murdering," then does not saving the baby's soul negate that moral wrong? As absurd as this sounds, here is an anecdote from Christian apologist William Lane Craig that, to me, demonstrates this thinking quite well and proves my point further:

    Moreover, if we believe, as I do, that God’s grace is extended to those who die in infancy or as small children, the death of these children was actually their salvation. We are so wedded to an earthly, naturalistic perspective that we forget that those who die are happy to quit this earth for heaven’s incomparable joy. Therefore, God does these children no wrong in taking their lives. (6)

    And furthermore, in the same article he justifies the slaughter of the Canaanites in this paragraph:

    But why take the lives of innocent children? The terrible totality of the destruction was undoubtedly related to the prohibition of assimilation to pagan nations on Israel’s part. In commanding complete destruction of the Canaanites, the Lord says, “You shall not intermarry with them, giving your daughters to their sons, or taking their daughters for your sons, for they would turn away your sons from following me, to serve other gods” (Deut 7.3-4). This command is part and parcel of the whole fabric of complex Jewish ritual law distinguishing clean and unclean practices. To the contemporary Western mind many of the regulations in Old Testament law seem absolutely bizarre and pointless: not to mix linen with wool, not to use the same vessels for meat and for milk products, etc. The overriding thrust of these regulations is to prohibit various kinds of mixing. Clear lines of distinction are being drawn: this and not that. These serve as daily, tangible reminders that Israel is a special people set apart for God Himself. (Ibid)

    Of course not every Christian or even Jew will agree with this (which would mean they take issue with the Bible lest they use a more liberal, figurative translation, which becomes subjective, can be applied to any part, and compromises the literal truth of the scriptures), but it bolsters my point concerning the outrageous justifications Christians will make to make sure the Bible maintains its authority and is in line with their modern moral convictions. Are these the kind of morals you uphold? These archaic practices are condoned when it would make more sense for modern Christianity to throw away the Old Testament. However, doing this leaves no foundation for Jesus and his teachings, as well as many of the prophecies and references the New Testament references, and vice versa, the many teachings that Christians use to claim the authenticity of the Bible.

    ReplyDelete
  24. In conclusion (Really? Done so soon?) . . .

    These are some very hard questions, and I certainly don't think I've done an adequate job addressing them here. For me, I can see serious holes on either side, however I believe one side relates to me more as a human being and my experiences, which flies in the face of scripture that tells me we are created either as "vessels of honor" or "vessels of dishonor" and "doth the clay reply to the potter 'why hast thou made me so?'" It seems my questions concerning the Bible and those within theology are treated as "not allowing God to fit into my presuppositions" or worse yet, "questioning the authority of God" (and I have been told both of these before). For me, these responses are not satisfying, but I won't go so far to say that God or a supremely intelligent being does not exist if I'm truly going to be fair.

    The existence of multiple theologies is also disheartening, e.g., Calvinism and its teachings, even though it does logically fit with the deterministic implications of the Bible as well as remedying other flaws through perseverance of the saints and federal/seminal headship that Armenian views and free will cannot uphold (e.g., in the Armenian view, you can lose your salvation through sin because it is not deterministic, meaning constant sanctification and "re-dedication" to Jesus, i.e., being saved repeatedly). Those that do not hold to a theology have no foundation for their beliefs, nor any kind of succinct translation for what or why they believe the way they do about the teachings of the Bible. This again is the utmost definition of unconditional faith.

    ReplyDelete
  25. And in continuing the idea of unconditional faith, how do you answer the age old question that god is God? How many other religions say their god is one with a capital "G"? I find it difficult to have such unconditional faith in just one when there are several religions that contain a god in human form who also taught great things and is worshiped as a god. How and why does one settle on just one and how much research and thought went into picking this one God out of all the others?

    But differences in theology do make sense to me--we would expect to see different schools of thought in literature and even in science, or any other area of human study. The difference is that these differences can never be resolved in the Bible; there is just no way to know. This is where you get the "when I get to heaven, I'm going to ask God . . ." Again, echoing a commentator, it is like putting a stamp of finality on one book and hoping that it will survive the test of time as an authoritative, final word on all human affairs.

    As I stated in my intro, I hope I haven't come across as offensive in my response. Tone does not come across well over written discussion such as this, and the last thing I want to read as is a new atheist or a Dawkins type. I can definitively say that if you make a good argument and show me what I'm missing that I will be happy to accept. I don't feel my arguments here are nearly at their best, nor free from fallacy by any means (and I can see this as I go through it). Currently, science has won me over in this regard and it took many years. I grew up attending only Christian schools and churches and was theologically able to defend my faith, but unable to adequately bypass scientific claims that clearly flew in the face of biblical teachings.

    I certainly can see how a God or supremely intelligent being could be responsible for the fine-tuned nature of the universe, and for me to rule it out entirely would also mean me committing an argument from ignorance; but I do not see how one can rule out all the other gods and stick with one, especially when so much evidence is against a particular doctrine like Christianity.

    References:

    1. Of the use of the Hebrew word "yom" meaning a literal, 24-hour day in the Bible: http://www.creationtoday.org/the-hebrew-yom-taking-one-day-at-a-time/

    2. Of geological evidence against a global flood: http://ncse.com/cej/1/1/fatal-flaws-flood-geology

    3. Of Isaac Asimov's "The Relativity of Wrong": http://hermiene.net/essays-trans/relativity_of_wrong.html

    4. Of physicist Sean Carroll's definition of the objective of science: http://www.npr.org/blogs/13.7/2010/05/04/126504492/you-can-t-derive-ought-from-is

    5. Of Einstein's Theory of General Relativity and how it holds up to modern experimentation (through the experiment of a white dwarf orbiting a neutron star): http://www.livescience.com/29062-einstein-relativity-tested-again.html.

    5.b Also, see here http://pubs.giss.nasa.gov/abs/co00100w.html and here http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2013/04/26/einstein-general-relativity-theory-white-dwarf-neutron-star_n_3157482.html for more information.

    6. Of the Judeo-Christian/William Lane Craig's justification of genocide in the passages concerning the slaughter of the Canaanites: http://www.reasonablefaith.org/slaughter-of-the-canaanites

    ReplyDelete